Switch to: References

Citations of:

Ex impossibili quodlibet sequitur

Medioevo 24:177-218 (1998)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Buridan on ‘Ex impossibili quodlibet’, ‘Ex contradictione quodlibet’, and ‘Ex falso quodlibet’.Wolfgang Lenzen - forthcoming - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy.
    Buridan endorsed the principles that any impossible, and a fortiori any self-contradictory, proposition entails each proposition. These principles are usually referred to as ‘Ex impossibili quodlibet’ (EIQ) and ‘Ex contradictione quodlibet’ (ECQ). Buridan further considered the instance ECCQ according to which any proposition follows from the conjunction of two contradictory propositions. Buridan showed how ECCQ can be proven by means the usual laws of conjunction and disjunction. Furthermore, he discovered that EIQ can be derived from ECCQ by means of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • John Buridan on Logical Consequence.Boaz Faraday Schuman - forthcoming - In Graziana Ciola & Milo Crimi (eds.), Validity Throughout History. Philosophia Verlag.
    If an argument is valid, it is impossible for its premises to be true, and its conclusion false. But how should we understand these notions of truth and impossibility? Here, I present the answers given by John Buridan (ca. 1300-60), showing (i) how he understands truth in his anti-realist metaphysics, and (ii) how he understands modality in connection with causal powers. In short: if an argument exists and is valid, there does not exist a power capable of making the premises (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ex impossibili quodlibet sequitur.Calvin G. Normore - 2015 - Vivarium 53 (2-4):353-371.
    _ Source: _Volume 53, Issue 2-4, pp 353 - 371 While agreeing with Professor D’Ors’ thesis that the notion of logical consequence cannot be exhaustively characterized, I depart from Professor d’Ors’ conclusion that the very notion of good consequence is primitive and can only be identified with the set of acceptable rules of inference, and from his conviction that modal notions such as necessity and impossibility are equivocal and gain such clarity as they have by their interaction with rules of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Seventeenth-Century Scholastic Syllogistics. Between Logic and Mathematics?Miroslav Hanke - 2020 - Review of Symbolic Logic 13 (2):219-248.
    The seventeenth century can be viewed as an era of (closely related) innovation in the formal and natural sciences and of paradigmatic diversity in philosophy (due to the coexistence of at least the humanist, the late scholastic, and the early modern tradition). Within this environment, the present study focuses on scholastic logic and, in particular, syllogistic. In seventeenth-century scholastic logic two different approaches to logic can be identified, one represented by the Dominicans Báñez, Poinsot, and Comas del Brugar, the other (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Richard Kilvington and the Theory of Obligations.Stephen Read - 2015 - Vivarium 53 (2-4):391-404.
    Kretzmann and Spade were led by Richard Kilvington’s proposed revisions to the rules of obligations in his discussion of the 47th sophism in his Sophismata to claim that the purpose of obligational disputations was the same as that of counterfactual reasoning. Angel d’Ors challenged this interpretation, realising that the reason for Kilvington’s revision was precisely that he found the art of obligation unsuited to the kind of reasoning which lay at the heart of the sophismatic argument. In his criticism, Kilvington (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)Studies on Walter Burley 1989-1997.Gerhard Krieger - 1999 - Vivarium 37 (1):94-100.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark