Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The Ethics of Lustration.Jens Meierhenrich - 2006 - Ethics and International Affairs 20 (1):99-120.
    One of the most important challenges for the occupation of Iraq has been making decisions about the status of people who were either responsible for or who passively benefited from the regime’s past injustices.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Kantian Peace and Liberal Peace: Three Concerns.Luigi Caranti - 2016 - Journal of Political Philosophy 24 (4):446-469.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Democratic Minimum: Is Democracy a Means to Global Justice?James Bohman - 2005 - Ethics and International Affairs 19 (1):101-116.
    I argue that transnational democracy provides the basis for a solution to the problem of the “democratic circle”—that in order for democracy to promote justice, it must already be just—at the international level. Transnational democracy could be a means to global justice. First, I briefly recount my argument for the “democratic minimum.” This minimum is freedom from domination, understood in a very specific sense. Employing Hannah Arendt's conception of freedom as “the capacity to begin,” the form of nondomination sufficient for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • The Limits of Kant’s Cosmopolitanism: Theory, Practice, and the Crisis in Syria.Matthew C. Altman - 2017 - Kantian Review 22 (2):179-204.
    Although Kant defends a cosmopolitan ideal, his philosophy is problematically vague regarding how to achieve it, which lends support to the empty formalism charge. How Kant would respond to the crisis in Syria reveals that judgement plays too central a role, because Kantian principles lead to equally reasonable but opposite conclusions on how to weigh the duty of hospitality to refugees against a state’s duty to its own citizens, the right of prevention towards ISIS against the duty not to harm (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Why Carl Schmitt (and others) got Kant wrong.Paola Romero - 2021 - Con-Textos Kantianos 1 (13):186-208.
    This essay traces the influence of Carl Schmitt on an interpretative tendency found in a number of contemporary readings of Kant’s political philosophy. This influence can be traced back to two basic commitments: the idea that Kant’s philosophy seeks to defend a pacifist and humanitarian ideal of history and progress, and that political conflict must, for this reason, be somehow pacified or eradicated. I argue that these ‘anti-conflict’ readings of Kant go astray in ignoring the systemic role conflict plays in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Luigi Caranti, Kant’s Political Legacy: Human Rights, Peace, Progress Cardiff: University of Wales Press, 2017 Pp. xii + 303 ISBN 9781783169795. [REVIEW]Carlos J. Pereira Di Salvo - 2018 - Kantian Review 23 (4):681-687.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kant, the republican peace, and moral guidance in international law.Cecelia Lynch - 1994 - Ethics and International Affairs 8:39–58.
    Lynch addresses the return to Immanuel Kant—a "prophet of progressive international reform"—and examines the relationship between the Kantian system of ethics and the development of international law in the post-Cold War era.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Kant on international distributive justice.Sylvie Loriaux - 2007 - Journal of Global Ethics 3 (3):281 – 301.
    This paper concentrates on the way Kant's distinction between duties of right and duties of virtue operates at the interstate level. I argue that his Right of Nations (V ölkerrecht) can be interpreted as a duty to establish a kind of interstate distributive justice (that is, as a duty to secure states in their independence and territorial possessions), which is called for to secure domestic distributive justice and to protect individuals' freedom and private property. Or at least this is 'ideal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Kant and the Supreme Proprietor: A Response.Anthony F. Lang - 2010 - Kantian Review 15 (2):78-89.
    Theories of global justice range from the utilitarian philosophy of Peter Singer to the institutional design arguments of Thomas Pogge. These works have grappled with a wide range of issues, but almost all of them have been driven by the recognition of two core problems: the huge numbers of people mired in poverty and the increasing levels of inequality. Much of this literature begins with these two problems and then proposes schemes to resolve them. This problem-solving approach to the issue (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Torture and democratic violence.Paul W. Kahn - 2009 - Ratio Juris 22 (2):244-259.
    Abstract. To understand the problem of torture in a democratic society, we have to take up a political-theological perspective. We must ask how violence creates political meaning. Torture is no more destructive and no more illiberal than other forms of political violence. The turn away from torture was not a turn away from violence, but a change in the locus of sacrifice: from scaffold to battlefield. Torture had been a ritual of mediation between sovereign and subject. Once sovereignty is located (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What is democratic reliability? Epistemic theories of democracy and the problem of reasonable disagreement.Felix Gerlsbeck - 2018 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 21 (2):218-241.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Machiavelli at 500: From Cynic to Vigilant Supporter of International Law.Andreas Follesdal - 2015 - Ratio Juris 28 (2):242-251.
    Machiavelli's 500-year-old treatise The Prince outlined the central features of the realist tradition in international relations. His premises led him to question the likelihood of efficacious and stable international law and international courts, a skepticism that has present-day proponents. Machiavelli's reluctance was due to a combination of features of human nature and a focus on anarchic features of the relations among states. This article challenges these assumptions and implications: Other interpretations of human nature are closer to Machiavelli's text, and current (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The end of History or the end of Democracy? National identity and the future of the nation-state.Wolf-Dieter Eberwein - 1994 - World Futures 42 (1):161-171.
    (1994). The end of History or the end of Democracy? National identity and the future of the nation‐state. World Futures: Vol. 42, No. 1-2, pp. 161-171.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ouroboros: Identity War as a Reaction to the Transformative Mission of Liberalism.Philip W. Reynolds - 2017 - Dissertation, University of Hawaiʻi at Mānoa
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark