Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The Idea of a Living Constitution.Aileen Kavanagh - 2003 - Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 16 (1):55-89.
    This article is a jurisprudential analysis of the idea of a ‘living Constitution’, as a common feature of the constitutional practice in democratic countries. The main argument of the article is that constitutional interpretation encompasses, rather than excludes the judicial power to develop and change the content of constitutional guarantees. The metaphor of the ‘living Constitution’ is appropriate to the nature of constitutional adjudication because it suggests gradual, incremental change on a case-by-case basis. While it is stressed that courts can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Law, ‘Ought’, and ‘Can’.Frederick Wilmot-Smith - 2023 - Ethics 133 (4):529-557.
    It is commonly held that “ought implies can.” If so, what constraints does that place on the law? Having provided an argument which allows the maxim to be used by lawyers, I consider the application of that argument to both primary and remedial legal duties. This, it turns out, gives us some reason to reconsider whether the maxim is sound. Further, even if the maxim is sound, it has less purchase on remedial duties than is commonly supposed.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Bright Lines in Juvenile Justice.Amy Berg - 2021 - Journal of Political Philosophy 29 (3):330-352.
    Journal of Political Philosophy, EarlyView.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Constitutions, rule following, and the crisis of constraint.Thomas P. Crocker & Michael P. Hodges - 2018 - Legal Theory 24 (1):3-39.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Criminal Law and Republican Liberty: Philip Pettit’s Account.Jeremy Horder - 2022 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 16 (1):193-213.
    Philip Pettit has made central to modern republican theory a distinctive account of freedom—republican freedom. On this account, I am not free solely because I can make choices without interference. I am truly free, only if that non-interference does not itself depend on another’s forbearance. Pettit believes that the principal justification for the traditional focus of the criminal law is that it constitutes a bulwark against domination. I will, in part, be considering the merits of this claim. Is the importance (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • State Estoppel.Dennis Klimchuk - 2020 - Law and Philosophy 39 (3):297-323.
    It is a recurring idea in the history of political philosophy that concepts and doctrines of private law are illuminative of public law and political philosophy. Central among these are contract and the trust. In this paper, I consider the prospects of a third: estoppel. The public law context in which estoppel is most commonly invoked is criminal law, and there especially in the service of understanding the defenses of entrapment and what I call officially induced mistake of law. My (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark