Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The pulse of modernism: experimental physiology and aesthetic avant-gardes circa 1900.Robert Michael Brain - 2008 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 39 (3):393-417.
    When discussing the changing sense of reality around 1900 in the cultural arts the lexicon of early modernism reigns supreme. This essay contends that a critical condition for the possibility of many of the turn of the century modernist movements in the arts can be found in exchange of instruments, concepts, and media of representation between the sciences and the arts. One route of interaction came through physiological aesthetics, the attempt to ‘elucidate physiologically the nature of our Aesthetic feelings’ and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Geometry and analysis in Euler’s integral calculus.Giovanni Ferraro, Maria Rosaria Enea & Giovanni Capobianco - 2017 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 71 (1):1-38.
    Euler developed a program which aimed to transform analysis into an autonomous discipline and reorganize the whole of mathematics around it. The implementation of this program presented many difficulties, and the result was not entirely satisfactory. Many of these difficulties concerned the integral calculus. In this paper, we deal with some topics relevant to understand Euler’s conception of analysis and how he developed and implemented his program. In particular, we examine Euler’s contribution to the construction of differential equations and his (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Educational Reform and the Birth of a Mathematical Community in Revolutionary France, 1790–1815.Eduard Glas - 2003 - Science & Education 12 (1):75-89.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Geometry and analysis in Anastácio da Cunha’s calculus.João Caramalho Domingues - 2023 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 77 (6):579-600.
    It is well known that over the eighteenth century the calculus moved away from its geometric origins; Euler, and later Lagrange, aspired to transform it into a “purely analytical” discipline. In the 1780 s, the Portuguese mathematician José Anastácio da Cunha developed an original version of the calculus whose interpretation in view of that process presents challenges. Cunha was a strong admirer of Newton (who famously favoured geometry over algebra) and criticized Euler’s faith in analysis. However, the fundamental propositions of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • In Honour of Kirsti Andersen.Jesper Lützen & Henrik Kragh Sørensen - 2010 - Centaurus 52 (1):1-3.
    During the first half of the nineteenth century, mathematical analysis underwent a transition from a predominantly formula-centred practice to a more concept-centred one. Central to this development was the reorientation of analysis originating in Augustin-Louis Cauchy's (1789–1857) treatment of infinite series in his Cours d’analyse. In this work, Cauchy set out to rigorize analysis, thereby critically examining and reproving central analytical results. One of Cauchy's first and most ardent followers was the Norwegian Niels Henrik Abel (1802–1829) who vowed to shed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Lagrange’s theory of analytical functions and his ideal of purity of method.Marco Panza & Giovanni Ferraro - 2012 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 66 (2):95-197.
    We reconstruct essential features of Lagrange’s theory of analytical functions by exhibiting its structure and basic assumptions, as well as its main shortcomings. We explain Lagrange’s notions of function and algebraic quantity, and we concentrate on power-series expansions, on the algorithm for derivative functions, and the remainder theorem—especially on the role this theorem has in solving geometric and mechanical problems. We thus aim to provide a better understanding of Enlightenment mathematics and to show that the foundations of mathematics did not, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The foundational aspects of Gauss’s work on the hypergeometric, factorial and digamma functions.Giovanni Ferraro - 2007 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 61 (5):457-518.
    In his writings about hypergeometric functions Gauss succeeded in moving beyond the restricted domain of eighteenth-century functions by changing several basic notions of analysis. He rejected formal methodology and the traditional notions of functions, complex numbers, infinite numbers, integration, and the sum of a series. Indeed, he thought that analysis derived from a few, intuitively given notions by means of other well-defined concepts which were reducible to intuitive ones. Gauss considered functions to be relations between continuous variable quantities while he (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations