Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. On the compatibility of connectionist and classical models.John Hawthorne - 1989 - Philosophical Psychology 2 (1):5-16.
    This paper presents considerations in favour of the view that traditional (classical) architectures can be seen as emergent features of connectionist networks with distributed representation. A recent paper by William Bechtel (1988) which argues for a similar conclusion is unsatisfactory in that it fails to consider whether the compositional syntax and semantics attributed to mental representations by classical models can emerge within a connectionist network. The compatibility of the two paradigms hinges largely, I suggest, on how this question is answered. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • A worthy enterprise injured by overinterpretation and misrepresentation.Marc D. Hauser & Jon Sakata - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):638-638.
    The synthetic position adopted by Müller is weakened by a large number of overinterpretations and misrepresentations, together with a caricatured view of innateness and modularity.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Like the breathability of air: Embodied embedded communication.Willem F. G. Haselager - 2012 - Pragmatics and Cognition 20 (2):263-274.
    I present experimental and computational research, inspired by the perspective of Embodied Embedded Cognition, concerning various aspects of language as supporting Everett's interactionist view of language. Based on earlier and ongoing work, I briefly illustrate the contribution of the environment to the systematicity displayed in linguistic performance, the importance of joint attention for the development of a shared vocabulary, the role of (limited) traveling for language diversification, the function of perspective taking in social communication, and the bodily nature of understanding (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Connectionism, systematicity, and the frame problem.W. F. G. Haselager & J. F. H. Van Rappard - 1998 - Minds and Machines 8 (2):161-179.
    This paper investigates connectionism's potential to solve the frame problem. The frame problem arises in the context of modelling the human ability to see the relevant consequences of events in a situation. It has been claimed to be unsolvable for classical cognitive science, but easily manageable for connectionism. We will focus on a representational approach to the frame problem which advocates the use of intrinsic representations. We argue that although connectionism's distributed representations may look promising from this perspective, doubts can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Reduction, explanatory extension, and the mind/brain sciences.Valerie Gray Hardcastle - 1992 - Philosophy of Science 59 (3):408-28.
    In trying to characterize the relationship between psychology and neuroscience, the trend has been to argue that reductionism does not work without suggesting a suitable substitute. I offer explanatory extension as a good model for elucidating the complex relationship among disciplines which are obviously connected but which do not share pragmatic explanatory features. Explanatory extension rests on the idea that one field can "illuminate" issues that were incompletely treated in another. In this paper, I explain how this "illumination" would work (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Performative Utterances: Seven Puzzles.Robert Harnish - 2007 - Lodz Papers in Pragmatics 3:3-21.
    Performative Utterances: Seven Puzzles It was John Austin who introduced the word "performative" into the philosophy of language and linguistics. His original idea was that there are utterances which are more correctly characterized as doing something rather than stating something. Austin wrote: "when I say ‘I do’, I am not reporting on a marriage, I am indulging in it." As is well known, Austin went on to work out this notion of a performative utterance in a number of directions, but (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Computation is just interpretable symbol manipulation; cognition isn't.Stevan Harnad - 1994 - Minds and Machines 4 (4):379-90.
    Computation is interpretable symbol manipulation. Symbols are objects that are manipulated on the basis of rules operating only on theirshapes, which are arbitrary in relation to what they can be interpreted as meaning. Even if one accepts the Church/Turing Thesis that computation is unique, universal and very near omnipotent, not everything is a computer, because not everything can be given a systematic interpretation; and certainly everything can''t be givenevery systematic interpretation. But even after computers and computation have been successfully distinguished (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • On the obvious treatment of connectionism.Stephen José Hanson - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):38-39.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Building on prior knowledge without building it in.Steven S. Hansen, Andrew K. Lampinen, Gaurav Suri & James L. McClelland - 2017 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 40.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Representational redescription, memory, and connectionism.P. J. Hampson - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):721-721.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Rule acquisition and variable binding: Two sides of the same coin.P. J. Hampson - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):462-462.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Things and pictures of things: Are perceptual processes invariant across cultures?Diane F. Halpern - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):84-85.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Processing capacity defined by relational complexity: Implications for comparative, developmental, and cognitive psychology.Graeme S. Halford, William H. Wilson & Steven Phillips - 1998 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 21 (6):803-831.
    Working memory limits are best defined in terms of the complexity of the relations that can be processed in parallel. Complexity is defined as the number of related dimensions or sources of variation. A unary relation has one argument and one source of variation; its argument can be instantiated in only one way at a time. A binary relation has two arguments, two sources of variation, and two instantiations, and so on. Dimensionality is related to the number of chunks, because (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   95 citations  
  • Fundamental differences between perception and cognition aside from cognitive penetrability.Graeme S. Halford & Trevor J. Hine - 2016 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 39.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Competing, or perhaps complementary, approaches to the dynamic-binding problem, with similar capacity limitations.Graeme S. Halford - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):461-462.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Similarity as transformation.Ulrike Hahn, Nick Chater & Lucy B. Richardson - 2003 - Cognition 87 (1):1-32.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Quantum algorithms: Philosophical lessons.Amit Hagar - 2007 - Minds and Machines 17 (2):233-247.
    I discuss the philosophical implications that the rising new science of quantum computing may have on the philosophy of computer science. While quantum algorithms leave the notion of Turing-Computability intact, they may re-describe the abstract space of computational complexity theory hence militate against the autonomous character of some of the concepts and categories of computer science.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Systematicity in connectionist language learning.Robert F. Hadley - 1994 - Mind and Language 9 (3):247-72.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Systematicity revisited.Robert F. Hadley - 1994 - Mind and Language 9 (4):431-44.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Systematicity Revisited: Reply to Christiansen and Chater and Niklasson and van Gelder.Robert F. Hadley - 1994 - Mind and Language 9 (4):431-444.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Strong semantic systematicity from Hebbian connectionist learning.Robert F. Hadley & M. B. Hayward - 1997 - Minds and Machines 7 (1):1-55.
    Fodor's and Pylyshyn's stand on systematicity in thought and language has been debated and criticized. Van Gelder and Niklasson, among others, have argued that Fodor and Pylyshyn offer no precise definition of systematicity. However, our concern here is with a learning based formulation of that concept. In particular, Hadley has proposed that a network exhibits strong semantic systematicity when, as a result of training, it can assign appropriate meaning representations to novel sentences (both simple and embedded) which contain words in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Strong Semantic Systematicity from Hebbian Connectionist Learning.Robert Hadley & Michael Hayward - 1997 - Minds and Machines 7 (1):1-37.
    Fodor's and Pylyshyn's stand on systematicity in thought and language has been debated and criticized. Van Gelder and Niklasson, among others, have argued that Fodor and Pylyshyn offer no precise definition of systematicity. However, our concern here is with a learning based formulation of that concept. In particular, Hadley has proposed that a network exhibits strong semantic systematicity when, as a result of training, it can assign appropriate meaning representations to novel sentences (both simple and embedded) which contain words in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • On the proper treatment of semantic systematicity.Robert F. Hadley - 2004 - Minds and Machines 14 (2):145-172.
    The past decade has witnessed the emergence of a novel stance on semantic representation, and its relationship to context sensitivity. Connectionist-minded philosophers, including Clark and van Gelder, have espoused the merits of viewing hidden-layer, context-sensitive representations as possessing semantic content, where this content is partially revealed via the representations'' position in vector space. In recent work, Bodén and Niklasson have incorporated a variant of this view of semantics within their conception of semantic systematicity. Moreover, Bodén and Niklasson contend that they (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Explaining Systematicity: A Reply to Kenneth Aizawa.Robert F. Hadley - 1997 - Minds and Machines 7 (4):571-579.
    In his discussion of results which I (with Michael Hayward) recently reported in this journal, Kenneth Aizawa takes issue with two of our conclusions, which are: (a) that our connectionist model provides a basis for explaining systematicity “within the realm of sentence comprehension, and subject to a limited range of syntax” (b) that the model does not employ structure-sensitive processing, and that this is clearly true in the early stages of the network's training. Ultimately, Aizawa rejects both (a) and (b) (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Cognition, systematicity, and nomic necessity.Robert F. Hadley - 1997 - Mind and Language 12 (2):137-53.
    In their provocative 1988 paper, Fodor and Pylyshyn issued a formidable challenge to connectionists, i.e. to provide a non‐classical explanation of the empirical phenomenon of systematicity in cognitive agents. Since the appearance of F&P's challenge, a number of connectionist systems have emerged which prima facie meet this challenge. However, Fodor and McLaughlin (1990) advance an argument, based upon a general principle of nomological necessity, to show that one of these systems (Smolensky's) could not satisfy the Fodor‐Pylyshyn challenge. Yet, if Fodor (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Cognition, Systematicity and Nomic Necessity.Robert F. Hadley - 1997 - Mind and Language 12 (2):137-153.
    In their provocative 1988 paper, Fodor and Pylyshyn issued a formidable challenge to connectionists, i.e. to provide a non‐classical explanation of the empirical phenomenon of systematicity in cognitive agents. Since the appearance of F&P's challenge, a number of connectionist systems have emerged which prima facie meet this challenge. However, Fodor and McLaughlin (1990) advance an argument, based upon a general principle of nomological necessity, to show that one of these systems (Smolensky's) could not satisfy the Fodor‐Pylyshyn challenge. Yet, if Fodor (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Connectionism and novel combinations of skills: Implications for cognitive architecture. [REVIEW]Robert F. Hadley - 1999 - Minds and Machines 9 (2):197-221.
    In the late 1980s, there were many who heralded the emergence of connectionism as a new paradigm – one which would eventually displace the classically symbolic methods then dominant in AI and Cognitive Science. At present, there remain influential connectionists who continue to defend connectionism as a more realistic paradigm for modeling cognition, at all levels of abstraction, than the classical methods of AI. Not infrequently, one encounters arguments along these lines: given what we know about neurophysiology, it is just (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Connectionism, explicit rules, and symbolic manipulation.Robert F. Hadley - 1993 - Minds and Machines 3 (2):183-200.
    At present, the prevailing Connectionist methodology forrepresenting rules is toimplicitly embody rules in neurally-wired networks. That is, the methodology adopts the stance that rules must either be hard-wired or trained into neural structures, rather than represented via explicit symbolic structures. Even recent attempts to implementproduction systems within connectionist networks have assumed that condition-action rules (or rule schema) are to be embodied in thestructure of individual networks. Such networks must be grown or trained over a significant span of time. However, arguments (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The problem with appealing to history in defining neural representations.Ori Hacohen - 2022 - European Journal for Philosophy of Science 12 (3):1-17.
    Representations seem to play a major role in many neuroscientific explanations. Philosophers have long attempted to properly define what it means for a neural state to be a representation of a specific content. Teleosemantic theories of content which characterize representations, in part, by appealing to a historical notion of function, are often regarded as our best path towards an account of neural representations. This paper points to the anti-representationalist consequences of these accounts. I argue that assuming such teleosemantic views will (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Tensor products and split-level architecture: Foundational issues in the classicism-connectionism debate.Marcello Guarini - 1996 - Philosophy of Science 63 (3):S239-S247.
    This paper responds to criticisms levelled by Fodor, Pylyshyn, and McLaughlin against connectionism. Specifically, I will rebut the charge that connectionists cannot account for representational systematicity without implementing a classical architecture. This will be accomplished by drawing on Paul Smolensky's Tensor Product model of representation and on his insights about split-level architectures.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cognitive Science.Rick Grush - 2002 - In Peter Machamer & Michael Silberstein (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Science. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 272–289.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Introduction Historical Background: Behaviorism and the Cognitive Revolution Current Topics Future Directions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Beyond connectionist versus classical Al: A control theoretic perspective on development and cognitive science.Rick Grush - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):720-720.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Self-organizing neural models of categorization, inference and synchrony.Stephen Grossberg - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):460-461.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • No threat to modularity.Yosef Grodzinsky & Uri Hadar - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):70-71.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Neurobiological approaches to language: Falsehoods and fallacies.Yosef Grodzinsky - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):637-637.
    The conclusion that language is not really innate or modular is based on several fallacies. I show that the target article confuses communicative skills with linguistic abilities, and that its discussion of brain/language relations is replete with factual errors. I also criticize its attempt to contrast biological and linguistic principles. Finally, I argue that no case is made for the “alternative” approach proposed here.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Linking brain to mind in normal behavior and schizophrenia.Stephen Grossberg - 2003 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (1):90-90.
    To understand schizophrenia, a linking hypothesis is needed that shows how brain mechanisms lead to behavioral functions in normals, and also how breakdowns in these mechanisms lead to behavioral symptoms of schizophrenia. Such a linking hypothesis is now available that complements the discussion offered by Phillips & Silverstein (P&S).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Distributed neural blackboards could be more attractive.André Grüning & Alessandro Treves - 2006 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 29 (1):79-80.
    The target article demonstrates how neurocognitive modellers should not be intimidated by challenges such as Jackendoff's and should explore neurally plausible implementations of linguistic constructs. The next step is to take seriously insights offlered by neuroscience, including the robustness allowed by analogue computation with distributed representations and the power of attractor dynamics in turning analogue into nearly discrete operations.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Analogue Models and Universal Machines. Paradigms of Epistemic Transparency in Artificial Intelligence.Hajo Greif - 2022 - Minds and Machines 32 (1):111-133.
    The problem of epistemic opacity in Artificial Intelligence is often characterised as a problem of intransparent algorithms that give rise to intransparent models. However, the degrees of transparency of an AI model should not be taken as an absolute measure of the properties of its algorithms but of the model’s degree of intelligibility to human users. Its epistemically relevant elements are to be specified on various levels above and beyond the computational one. In order to elucidate this claim, I first (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Against eliminative materialism: From folk psychology to volkerpsychologie.John D. Greenwood - 1992 - Philosophical Psychology 5 (4):349-68.
    In this paper it is argued that we would not be logically obliged or rationally inclined to reject the ontology of contentful psychological states postulated by folk psychology even if the explanations advanced by folk psychology turned out to be generally inaccurate or inadequate. Moreover, it is argued that eliminativists such as Paul Churchland do not establish that folk psychological explanations are, or are likely to prove, generally inaccurate or inadequate. Most of Churchland's arguments—based upon developments within connectionist neuroscience—only cast (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The historical basis of scientific discovery.Gerd Grasshoff - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):545-546.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Speaking of language: Thoughts on associations.Susan Graham & Diane Poulin-Dubois - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):636-636.
    Müller attempts to downplay cases of dissociation between language and cognition as evidence against the modularity of language. We review cases of associations between verbal and nonverbal abilities as further evidence against the notion of language as an autonomous subsystem. We also point out a discrepancy between his proposal of homologies between nonhuman primates' communication and human language and recent proposals on the evolution of language.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dissociation, self-attribution, and redescription.George Graham - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):719-719.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Connectionism in Pavlovian harness.George Graham - 1987 - Southern Journal of Philosophy (Suppl.) 73 (S1):73-91.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Connectionism in Pavlovian Harness.George Graham - 1988 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 26 (S1):73-91.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Representation and Processing of Coreference in Discourse.Peter C. Gordon & Randall Hendrick - 1998 - Cognitive Science 22 (4):389-424.
    A model is presented that addresses both the distribution and comprehension of different forms of referring expressions in language. This model is expressed in a formalism (Kamp & Reyle, 1993) that uses interpretive rules to map syntactic representations onto representations of discourse. Basic interpretive rules are developed for names, pronouns, definite descriptions, and quantified descriptions. These rules are triggered by syntactic input and interact dynamically with representations of discourse to establish reference and coreference. This interaction determines the ease with which (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Familial language impairment: The evidence.Myrna Gopnik - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):635-636.
    Müller argues that general cognitive skills and linguistic skills are not necessarily independent. However, cross-linguistic evidence from an inherited specific language disorder affecting productive rules suggests significant degrees of modularity, innateness, and universality of language. Confident claims about the overall nature of such a complex system still await more interdisciplinary research.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Rube Goldberg machine par excellence.Myrna Gopnik - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):734-735.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cognitive coordination deficits: A necessary but not sufficient factor in the development of schizophrenia.Diane C. Gooding & Jacqueline G. Braun - 2003 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (1):89-90.
    The Phillips & Silverstein model of NMDA-mediated coordination deficits provides a useful heuristic for the study of schizophrenic cognition. However, the model does not specifically account for the development of schizophrenia-spectrum disorders. The P&S model is compared to Meehl's seminal model of schizotaxia, schizotypy, and schizophrenia, as well as the model of schizophrenic cognitive dysfunction posited by McCarley and colleagues.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Redes neurais e representação mental: um ensaio sobre harmonia e racionalidade.Maria Eunice Quilici Gonzales - 1991 - Trans/Form/Ação 14:93-108.
    We develop an analysis of the notion of mental representation, in the domain of visual perception, from a Cognitive Science perspective. Emphasis is given on a Connectionist view, according to which mental representations are emergent properties of the interaction between brain-like systems and structured light in the environment. We suggest that such a notion of mental representation indicates a way out of an ancient dispute between Representationalism and Eliminativism regarding the existence of mental representation in the human perceptual system.We develop (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Wherein is Human Cognition Systematic?Antoni Gomila, David Travieso & Lorena Lobo - 2012 - Minds and Machines 22 (2):101-115.
    The “systematicity argument” has been used to argue for a classical cognitive architecture (Fodor in The Language of Thought. Harvester Press, London, 1975, Why there still has to be a language of thought? In Psychosemantics, appendix. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 135–154, 1987; Fodor and Pylyshyn in Cognition 28:3–71, 1988; Aizawa in The systematicity arguments. Kluwer Academic Press, Dordrecht, 2003). From the premises that cognition is systematic and that the best/only explanation of systematicity is compositional structure, it concludes that cognition is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations