Switch to: References

Citations of:

Philosophy of science and its discontents

Boulder: Westview Press (1989)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Why is the reliability of peer review so low?Donald Laming - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):154-156.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Do we really want more “reliable” reviewers?Helena Chmura Kraemer - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):152-154.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Japan's reception of science in the light of social epistemology.Tadashi Kobayashi - 1999 - Social Epistemology 13 (3 & 4):251 – 256.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • In defense of expertise; on its location in social epistemology.Hidetoshi Kihara - 1999 - Social Epistemology 13 (3 & 4):269 – 272.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Confusion between reviewer reliability and wise editorial and funding decisions.Charles A. Kiesler - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):151-152.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Response to Slezak: Nein, ich verstehe nicht.William Keith - 1990 - Social Epistemology 4 (4):361 – 367.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Argument practices.William Keith - 1995 - Argumentation 9 (1):163-179.
    The move to Postmodernism in argumentation is often predicated on the rejection of the formal basis of argument in logic. While this rejection may be justified, and is widely discussed in the literature, the loss of logic creates problems that a Postmodern theory of argument must address without recourse to logic and its attendant modernist assumptions. This essay argues that conceiving of argument in terms ofpractices will address the key problematics of Postmodernism without abandoning those features of argumentation that make (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On begging the question when naturalizing norms.Leonard D. Katz - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):21-22.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Gift versus Trade: On the Culture of Science Communication.Ilya Kasavin - 2019 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 49 (6):453-472.
    This article aims at a critical reevaluation of the trading zone concept. It starts from a case study of the Faraday–Whewell collaboration in coming to terms with electrolysis experiments. The case is supposed to be an example of a trade zone of science/philosophy interaction though it demonstrates the unequal nature of the “trade.” This requires the analysis to log in some details concerning Galison’s metaphor of trading zones, which reveals its market-oriented connotations. The following criticism of the market metaphor for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The logic of intervention in knowledge production.Osamu Kanamori - 1999 - Social Epistemology 13 (3 & 4):263 – 267.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Departing from consequentialism versus departing from decision theory.Frank Jackson - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):21-21.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Elicitation rules and incompatible goals.Julie R. Irwin - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):20-21.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Copernican Revolution revisited: paradigm, metaphor and incommensurability in the history of science- Blumenberg's response to Kuhn and Davidson.David Ingram - 1993 - History of the Human Sciences 6 (4):11-35.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Truth or consequences.John Heil - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):19-20.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Referee agreement in context.Lowell L. Hargens - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):150-151.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Consequences of consequentialism.Rick Grush - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):18-19.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is there an alternative to peer review?Richard Greene - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):149-150.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Replication, reliability and peer review: A case study.Michael E. Gorman - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):149-149.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Book Review: Knowledge. The Philosophical Quest in History, by Steve FullerFullerSteveKnowledge. The Philosophical Quest in History, New York, NY, Routledge, 2015. 304 pp., $54.95, ISBN 9781844658183. [REVIEW]Iván E. Gómez-Aguilar - 2017 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 47 (1):86-92.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Moral errors.Clark Glymour - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):17-18.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the hermeneutic fore-structure of scientific research.Dimitri Ginev - 1999 - Continental Philosophy Review 32 (2):143-168.
    The paper provides an overview of the hermeneutic and phenomenological context from which the idea of a “constitutional analysis” of science originated. It analyzes why the approach to “hermeneutic fore-structure of scientific research” requires to transcend the distinction between the context of justification and the context of discovery. By incorporating this approach into an integral “postmetaphysical philosophy of science”, I argue that one can avoid the radical empiricism of recent science studies, while also preventing the analysis of science's discursive practices (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Against the politics of postmodern philosophy of science.Dimitri Ginev - 2005 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 19 (2):191 – 208.
    This paper discusses the tenets of the politics of postmodern philosophy of science. At issue are Rouse's version of naturalism and his reading of Quine's distinction between the indeterminacy of translation and the underdetermination of theories by empirical evidence. I argue that the postmodern approach to science's research practices as patterns of interaction within the world is not in line with the naturalistic account Rouse aims at. I focus also on Rouse's readings of Heidegger's existential conception of science and Kuhn's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • On forecasting validity and finessing reliability.J. Barnard Gilmore - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):148-149.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Who hid the body? Rouse, Roth, and Woolgar on social epistemology.Steve Fuller - 1991 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 34 (3-4):391 – 400.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Why Practice Does Not Make Perfect: Some Additional Support for Turner‘s Social Theory of Practices. [REVIEW]Steve Fuller - 1997 - Human Studies 20 (3):315-323.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The unended Quest for legitimacy in science.Steve W. Fuller - 2003 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 33 (4):472-478.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The social epistemologist in search of a position from which to argue.Steve Fuller - 1994 - Argumentation 8 (2):163-183.
    The relevance of Fuller's version of social epistemology to argumentation theory is highlighted, in response to critics who claim that I am not sufficiently critical of the social grounds of knowledge production. Responding to Lyne, I first consider the strengths and weaknesses of relying on economic images to capture the social. Then, I tackle two contrary objections: Brian Baigrie claims social epistemology is “not social enough,” while Angelo Corlett wonders whether it may be “too social.” Finally, I counter Malcolm Ashmore, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Sphere of Critical Thinking in a Post-Epistemic World.Steve Fuller - 1994 - Informal Logic 16 (1).
    Just as political theorists have long argued that democracy is viable only in communities of certain sizes and shapes, perhaps epistemologists should also entertain the idea that knowledge is possible only within certain social parameters-ones which today's world may have exceeded. This is what I mean by the "postepistemic" society. I understand an "epistemic society" in Popperian terms as an environment that fosters the spirit of conjectures and refutations. After castigating analytic philosophers for their failure to see this point, I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Thinking the Unthinkable as a Radical Scientific Project.Steve Fuller - 2010 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 22 (4):397-413.
    Philip Tetlock underestimates the import of his own Expert Political Judgment. It is much more than a critical scientific evaluation of the accuracy and consistency of political pundits. It also offers a blueprint for challenging expertise more generally-in the name of scientific advancement. “Thinking the unthinkable”-a strategy Tetlock employs when he gets experts to consider counterfactual scenarios that are far from their epistemic comfort zones-has had explosive consequences historically for both knowledge and morality by extending our sense of what is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Higher Whitewash.Steve Fuller - 2014 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 44 (1):86-101.
    An assessment of Joel Isaac’s recent, well-researched attempt to provide a context for the emergence of Kuhn’s The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. That context consisted in the open space for cross-disciplinary projects between the natural and social sciences that existed at Harvard during the presidency of James Bryant Conant, from the early 1930s to the early 1950s. Isaac’s work at the Harvard archives adds interesting detail to a story whose general contours are already known. In particular, he reinforces the view (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Toward a Philosophy of Science Accounting: A Critical Rendering of Instrumental Rationality.Steve Fuller - 1994 - Science in Context 7 (3):591-621.
    The ArgumentI argue that “social epistemology” can be usefully reformulated as a philosophy of science accounting, specifically one that fosters a critical form of instrumental rationality. I begin by observing that philosophical and sociological species of “science accountancy” can be compared along two dimensions; constructive versus deconstve; reflexive versus unreflexive. The social epistemologist proposes a constructive and reflixive accounting for science. This possibility has been obscured, probably because of the persuasiveness of the Frankfulrt School's portrayal of “critical” and “instrumental” rationalities (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Response to the japanese social epistemologists: Some ways forward for the 21st century.Steve Fuller - 1999 - Social Epistemology 13 (3 & 4):273 – 302.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Symmetry as a Guide to Post-truth Times: A Response to Lynch.Steve Fuller - 2021 - Analyse & Kritik 43 (2):395-411.
    William Lynch has provided an informed and probing critique of my embrace of the post-truth condition, which he understands correctly as an extension of the normative project of social epistemology. This article roughly tracks the order of Lynch’s paper, beginning with the vexed role of the ‘normative’ in Science and Technology Studies, which originally triggered my version of social epistemology 35 years ago and has been guided by the field’s ‘symmetry principle’. Here the pejorative use of ‘populism’ to mean democracy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Review essay: The philosophical buck stops here.Steve Fuller - 2006 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 36 (3):355-366.
    George Reisch documents how the logical positivists adapted to their émigré status in the United States by relinquishing their leftist political ambitions and turning into the analytic philosophy establishment that persists to this day. However, there are also deep-seated tendencies in US intellectual history that provide reasons for thinking that the positivists’ progressive projects would never have taken hold—even if the FBI were not keeping the positivists under surveillance. These tendencies are manifested in the striking ineffectuality of US philosophers in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Peer review is not enough: Editors must work with librarians to ensure access to research.Steve Fuller - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):147-148.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kuhnenstein: Or, the importance of being read.Steve Fuller - 2005 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 35 (4):480-498.
    I respond to Rupert Read's highly critical review of my Kuhn vs Popper: The Struggle for the Soul Science . In contrast to my pro-Popper take on the debate, Read promotes a Wittgenstein-inflected Kuhn, whom I dub "Kuhnenstein." Kuhnenstein is largely the figment of Read's—and others'—fertile philosophical imagination as channeled through scholastic philosophical practice. Contra Read, I argue that Kuhnenstein provides not only a poor basis for social epistemology but Kuhnenstein's prominence itself exemplifies a poor social epistemology for philosophy. Nevertheless, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Is consequentialism better regarded as a form of reasoning or as a pattern of behavior?Steve Fuller - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):16-17.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Evidence? What Evidence?Steve Fuller - 2011 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 41 (4):567-573.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Divining the Future of Social Theory: From Theology to Rhetoric Via Social Epistemology.Steve Fuller - 1998 - European Journal of Social Theory 1 (1):107-126.
    The fertility of contemporary social theory is matched only by its problematic relationship to its past. The future of social theory therefore lies with a renegotiation of that relationship. I begin by unearthing the theological origins of theorizing and its secularization as epistemology in the 19th century. I then provide an account of the recent renaissance in social theory - epitomized by the various `structure-agency' debates - that reveals its intellectual kinship to scholastic theology. I diagnose this scholasticism in terms (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Book Review: Increasing Science’s Governability: Response to Hans Radder. [REVIEW]Steve Fuller - 2000 - Science, Technology, and Human Values 25 (4):527-534.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Book Review: Increasing Science’s Governability: Response to Hans Radder. [REVIEW]Steve Fuller - 2000 - Science, Technology, and Human Values 25 (4):545-552.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Author’s response.Steve Fuller - 1998 - Metascience 7 (2):316-319.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • 1916 and all that: The tale of two titans.Steve Fuller - 1991 - Knowledge, Technology & Policy 4 (4):79-84.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Consequentialism and utility theory.Deborah Frisch - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):16-16.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Journal availability and the quality of published research.Jack M. Fletcher - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):146-147.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Normative and descriptive consequentialism.Jonathan St B. T. Evans - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):15-16.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • When nonreliability of reviews indicates solid science.Douglas Lee Eckberg - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):145-146.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Why care where moral intuitions come from?Susan Dwyer - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):14-15.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Socializing naturalized philosophy of science.Stephen M. Downes - 1993 - Philosophy of Science 60 (3):452-468.
    I propose an approach to naturalized philosophy of science that takes the social nature of scientific practice seriously. I criticize several prominent naturalistic approaches for adopting "cognitive individualism", which limits the study of science to an examination of the internal psychological mechanisms of scientists. I argue that this limits the explanatory capacity of these approaches. I then propose a three-level model of the social nature of scientific practice, and use the model to defend the claim that scientific knowledge is socially (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Book Review: Science. [REVIEW]Stephen M. Downes - 2000 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 30 (1):140-145.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark