Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Aristotle's Cognitive Science: Belief, Affect and Rationality.Ian Mccready-Flora - 2013 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 89 (2):394-435.
    I offer a novel interpretation of Aristotle's psychology and notion of rationality, which draws the line between animal and specifically human cognition. Aristotle distinguishes belief (doxa), a form of rational cognition, from imagining (phantasia), which is shared with non-rational animals. We are, he says, “immediately affected” by beliefs, but respond to imagining “as if we were looking at a picture.” Aristotle's argument has been misunderstood; my interpretation explains and motivates it. Rationality includes a filter that interrupts the pathways between cognition (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Desires, their objects, and the things leading to pursuit.Duane Long - 2024 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 67 (9):3169-3194.
    I offer a novel analysis of the relations between Aristotle's three species of desire – appetite, temper, and wish – and the three things he says in EN 2.3 lead to pursuit – the pleasant, the beneficial, and the noble. It has long been tempting to think that these trios line up with one another in some way, ideally relating their members in one-to-one fashion. One account, by John Cooper, has gathered prominent adherents, but other authors, notably Giles Pearson, have (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The common sense and sensibility: Anna Marmodoro: Aristotle on perceiving objects. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, 304 pp, £47.99 HB.Amitavo Islam - 2015 - Metascience 24 (3):491-496.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Aristotle’s Perceptual Objectivism.Michael Arsenault - forthcoming - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie.
    Objectivism about perceptible qualities like colors and sounds is the view that perceptible qualities are ontologically and conceptually independent from perception. We ordinarily think of Aristotle as an objectivist about perceptible qualities – even the arch-objectivist. Yet this consensus has long been threatened by various thorny passages, including especially De anima III.2, 425b26–426a28, which appear to suggest that Aristotle is no objectivist, but a subjectivist. I show that recent attempts to make sense of these passages by appeal to Aristotle’s three-stage (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark