Switch to: References

Citations of:

Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?

Analysis 23 (6):121-123 (1963)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. A topological model of epistemic intentionality.Joël Bradmetz - 2002 - Axiomathes 13 (2):127-146.
    Beyond their linguistic and rhetorical uses, the mental epistemic verbs to knowand to believe reveal a basic conceptual system for human intentionality and the theory of representational mind. Numerous studies, particularly in the field of child development, have been devoted to the conditions under which knowledge and belief are acquired. Upstream of this empirical approach, this paper proposes a topological model of the conceptual structure underlying the linguistic use of to know and to believe. A cusp model of catastrophe theory (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Traditional epistemology and naturalistic replies to its skeptical critics.James Bogen - 1985 - Synthese 64 (2):195 - 224.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Knowledge and the evidential conditional.James Bode - 1977 - Philosophical Studies 31 (5):337 - 344.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Beyond verisimilitude: A linguistically invariant basis for scientific progress.Eric Barnes - 1991 - Synthese 88 (3):309 - 339.
    This paper proposes a solution to David Miller's Minnesotan-Arizonan demonstration of the language dependence of truthlikeness (Miller 1974), along with Miller's first-order demonstration of the same (Miller 1978). It is assumed, with Peter Urbach, that the implication of these demonstrations is that the very notion of truthlikeness is intrinsically language dependent and thus non-objective. As such, truthlikeness cannot supply a basis for an objective account of scientific progress. I argue that, while Miller is correct in arguing that the number of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • A theory of rational decision in games.Michael Bacharach - 1987 - Erkenntnis 27 (1):17 - 55.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Epistemic comparative conditionals.Linton Wang - 2008 - Synthese 162 (1):133 - 156.
    The interest of epistemic comparative conditionals comes from the fact that they represent genuine ‘comparative epistemic relations’ between propositions, situations, evidences, abilities, interests, etc. This paper argues that various types of epistemic comparative conditionals uniformly represent comparative epistemic relations via the comparison of epistemic positions rather than the comparison of epistemic standards. This consequence is considered as a general constraint on a theory of knowledge attribution, and then further used to argue against the contextualist thesis that, in some cases, considering (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Social epistemology, contextualism and the division of labour.Christopher Smith - 2002 - Social Epistemology 16 (1):65 – 81.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Probabilistic foundations for operator logic.B. H. Slater - 1993 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 44 (3):517-530.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Some conclusive reasons against 'conclusive reasons'.George S. Pappas & Marshall Swain - 1973 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 51 (1):72 – 76.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Knowledge from gossip?Kevin Meeker - 1999 - Philosophia 27 (3-4):537-539.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Barbara Thayer‐Bacon on Knowers and the Known.Jim McKenzie - 2002 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 34 (3):301–319.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Oxford realism: Knowledge and perception II.Mathieu Marion - 2000 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 8 (3):485 – 519.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Is religious education possible? A philosophical investigation - by Michael hand.Jim Mackenzie - 2007 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 39 (7):787–794.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Evidence one does not possess.William G. Lycan - 1977 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 55 (2):114 – 126.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Argument and belief: Where we stand in the Keynesian tradition. [REVIEW]R. P. Loui - 1991 - Minds and Machines 1 (4):357-365.
    There is the idea that rational belief for a single individual can be constructed via a process of unilateral argument. To preempt antipathy between the AI communities that can claim the idea that rational belief can be so constructed, we trace the idea to the beginning of this century, to Keynes' dispute with Russell over logic and probability. We review how Keynesian ideas were revived in AI's work on non-monotonic reasoning and parallel developments in philosophical logic.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Facts: Particulars or information units?Angelika Kratzer - 2002 - Linguistics and Philosophy 25 (5-6):655-670.
    What are facts, situations, or events? When Situation Semantics was born in the eighties, I objected because I could not swallow the idea that situations might be chunks of information. For me, they had to be particulars like sticks or bricks. I could not imagine otherwise. The first manuscript of “An Investigation of the Lumps of Thought” that I submitted to Linguistics and Philosophy had a footnote where I distanced myself from all those who took possible situations to be units (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Actually knowing.Stephen Hetherington - 1998 - Philosophical Quarterly 48 (193):453-469.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Gettier and scepticism.Stephen Cade Hetherington - 1992 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 70 (3):277 – 285.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Gettieristic scepticism.Stephen Cade Hetherington - 1996 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74 (1):83 – 97.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Knowledge, and our position regarding God.Anthony Baxter - 1993 - Heythrop Journal 34 (2):137–159.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The (near) necessity of alternate possibilities for moral responsibility.Richard M. Glatz - 2008 - Philosophical Studies 139 (2):257-272.
    Harry Frankfurt has famously criticized the principle of alternate possibilities—the principle that an agent is morally responsible for performing some action only if able to have done otherwise than to perform it—on the grounds that it is possible for an agent to be morally responsible for performing an action that is inevitable for the agent when the reasons for which the agent lacks alternate possibilities are not the reasons for which the agent has acted. I argue that an incompatibilist about (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Computation, among other things, is beneath us.Selmer Bringsjord - 1994 - Minds and Machines 4 (4):469-88.
    What''s computation? The received answer is that computation is a computer at work, and a computer at work is that which can be modelled as a Turing machine at work. Unfortunately, as John Searle has recently argued, and as others have agreed, the received answer appears to imply that AI and Cog Sci are a royal waste of time. The argument here is alarmingly simple: AI and Cog Sci (of the Strong sort, anyway) are committed to the view that cognition (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • On Denying a Presupposition of Sellars' Problem:A Defense of Propositionalism.Jonathan Kvanvig - 2005 - Veritas – Revista de Filosofia da Pucrs 50 (4):173-190.
    There is a great divide between two approaches to epistemology over the past thirty to forty years. Some label the divide that between internalists and externalists, and that characterization may be accurate on some account of the distinction. I will pursue the divide from a different direction, in part because the literature on the distinction between internalism and externalism has become a mess, and I don’t want to clean up the mess here.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Expiring while the Doctors are Disputing. Principled Limits of Medical Knowledge and the Ontological Square.Ludger Jansen - 2015 - Angewandte Philosophie. Eine Internationale Zeitschrift 2 (1):69-88.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The surplus value of knowledge.Wolfgang Spohn - 2024 - Theoria 90 (2):208-224.
    The Meno problem, asking for the surplus value of knowledge beyond the value of true justified belief, was recently much treated within reliabilist and virtue epistemologies. The answers from formal epistemology, by contrast, are quite poor. This paper attempts to improve the score of formal epistemology by precisely explicating Timothy Williamson's suggestion that ‘present knowledge is less vulnerable than mere present true belief to rational undermining by future evidence’. It does so by combining Nozick's sensitivity analysis of knowledge with Spohn's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Pritchard, Luck, Risk, and a New Problem for Safety-Based Accounts of Knowledge.James Simpson - forthcoming - Acta Analytica:1-14.
    In this paper, I develop a serious new dilemma involving necessary truths for safety-based theories of knowledge, a dilemma that I argue safety theorists cannot resolve or avoid by relativizing safety to either the subject’s basis or method of belief formation in close worlds or to a set of related or sufficiently similar propositions. I develop this dilemma primarily in conversation with Duncan Pritchard’s well-known, oft-modeled safety-based theories of knowledge. I show that Pritchard’s well-regarded anti-luck virtue theory of knowledge and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Integrative design for thought-experiments.Daniel Dohrn & Angelica Mezzadri - 2024 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 47:e39.
    Integrative experiment design should be extended to thought-experiments. Thought-experiments are closely connected to “real” experiments. They are involved in devising the design space of theories and possible experiments. The latter may be partitioned into experiments to be really performed and mere thought-experiments. The proposed extension of integrative experiment design lends guidance to a more methodical performance of thought-experiments.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark