Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Semantic content: In defense of a network approach.Paul M. Churchland - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):139-140.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Plasticity: conceptual and neuronal.Paul M. Churchland - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):133-134.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Neuroscience and psychology: should the labor be divided?Patricia Smith Churchland - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):133-133.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cognitive and motor implications of mental imagery.Romeo Chua & Daniel J. Weeks - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):203-204.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The language faculty that wasn't: a usage-based account of natural language recursion.Morten H. Christiansen & Nick Chater - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6:150920.
    In the generative tradition, the language faculty has been shrinking—perhaps to include only the mechanism of recursion. This paper argues that even this view of the language faculty is too expansive. We first argue that a language faculty is difficult to reconcile with evolutionary considerations. We then focus on recursion as a detailed case study, arguing that our ability to process recursive structure does not rely on recursion as a property of the grammar, but instead emerge gradually by piggybacking on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Active symbols, limited storage and the power of natural intelligence.Eric Chown & Stephen Kaplan - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):442-443.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Re-membering cognition.Susan F. Chipman - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):441-442.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Re-evaluating concepts of biological function in clinical medicine: towards a new naturalistic theory of disease.Benjamin Chin-Yee & Ross E. G. Upshur - 2017 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 38 (4):245-264.
    Naturalistic theories of disease appeal to concepts of biological function, and use the notion of dysfunction as the basis of their definitions. Debates in the philosophy of biology demonstrate how attributing functions in organisms and establishing the function-dysfunction distinction is by no means straightforward. This problematization of functional ascription has undermined naturalistic theories and led some authors to abandon the concept of dysfunction, favoring instead definitions based in normative criteria or phenomenological approaches. Although this work has enhanced our understanding of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Précis of How monkeys see the world.Dorothy L. Cheney & Robert M. Seyfarth - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):135-147.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Is there a role for extraretinal factors in the maintenance of stability in a structured environment?Eugene Chekaluk - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):258-258.
    The calibration solution to the stability of the world despite eye movements depends, according to Bridgeman et al., upon a combination of three factors which presumably all need to operate to achieve the goal of stability. Although the authors admit (sect. 4.3, para. 5) that the relative contributions of retinal and extraretinal factors will depend on the particular viewing situation, Figure 5 (sect. 4.3) makes it clear in its representation that the role of perceptual factors is relatively minor compared to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Characterizing the mind of another species.Dorothy L. Cheney & Robert M. Seyfarth - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):172-182.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Beasts, Beliefs, Intentions, Norms.David Checkland - 2009 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 39 (S1):299-335.
    “Terms that have histories cannot be defined.” – Nietzsche“[T]he reality to which we were attending seemed to resist our thinking it.” – Cora Diamond[1] Much has been learned in recent decades about the behaviour and abilities of many species of non-human animals. Increasingly many who reflect on the abilities of languageless animals are uncomfortable with a once prevalent dichotomy of either assigning these abilities to the realm of mere mechanism or granting such creatures full rationality and more or less the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • After the Philosophy of Mind: Replacing Scholasticism with Science.Tony Chemero & Michael Silberstein - 2008 - Philosophy of Science 75 (1):1-27.
    We provide a taxonomy of the two most important debates in the philosophy of the cognitive and neural sciences. The first debate is over methodological individualism: is the object of the cognitive and neural sciences the brain, the whole animal, or the animal--environment system? The second is over explanatory style: should explanation in cognitive and neural science be reductionist-mechanistic, inter-level mechanistic, or dynamical? After setting out the debates, we discuss the ways in which they are interconnected. Finally, we make some (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   87 citations  
  • Understanding the imitation deficit in autism may lead to a more specific model of autism as an empathy disorder.Tony Charman - 2001 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 25 (1):29-30.
    Preston & de Waal are understandably cautious in applying their model to autism. They emphasise multiple cognitive impairments in autism, including prefrontal-executive, cerebellar-attention, and amygdala-emotion recognition deficits. Further empirical examination of imitation ability in autism may reveal deficits in the neural and cognitive basis of perception-action mapping that have a specific relation to the empathic deficit.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The naked truth about first-person knowledge.Michael Chandler & Jeremy Carpendale - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):36-37.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The diversity of variability.William D. Chapple - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):602-602.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Self-ascription without qualia: A case study.David J. Chalmers - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):35-36.
    In Section 5 of his interesting article, Goldman suggests that the consideration of imaginary cases can be valuable in the analysis of our psychological concepts. In particular, he argues that we can imagine a system that is isomorphic to us under any functional description, but which lacks qualitative mental states, such as pains and color sensations. Whether or not such a being is empirically possible, it certainly seems to be logically possible, or conceptually coherent. Goldman argues from this possibility to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Reconciling simplicity and likelihood principles in perceptual organization.Nick Chater - 1996 - Psychological Review 103 (3):566-581.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Position space and motor synergies: A comparative perspective.William D. Chapple - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):152-153.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mechanistic and rationalistic explanations are complementary.B. Chandrasekaran - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):489-491.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Computing the thinkable.David J. Chalmers - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):658-659.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Categorization, theories and folk psychology.Nick Chater - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):37-37.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • An ecological approach toward a unified theory of learning.William R. Charlesworth - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):142-143.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Archaeology and the cognitive sciences in the study of human evolution.Philip G. Chase - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):752-753.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Against a “mindless” account of perceptual expertise.Amit Chaturvedi - 2019 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 18 (3):509-531.
    According to Hubert Dreyfus’s famous claim that expertise is fundamentally “mindless,” experts in any domain perform most effectively when their activity is automatic and unmediated by concepts or cognitive processes like attention and memory. While several scholars have recently challenged the plausibility of Dreyfus’s “mindless” account of expertise for explaining a wide range of expert activities, there has been little consideration of the one form of expertise which might be most amenable to Dreyfus’s account – namely, perceptual expertise. Indeed, Dreyfus’s (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Clades, Capgras, and Perceptual Kinds.Jack Lyons - 2005 - Philosophical Topics 33 (1):185-206.
    I defend a moderate (neither extremely conservative nor extremely liberal) view about the contents of perception. I develop an account of perceptual kinds as perceptual similarity classes, which are convex regions in similarity space. Different perceivers will enjoy different perceptual kinds. I argue that for any property P, a perceptual state of O can represent something as P only if P is coextensive with some perceptual kind for O. 'Dog' and 'chair' will be perceptual kinds for most normal people, 'blackpool (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Visual attention and beyond.Kyle R. Cave - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):400-400.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • There's more to mental states than meets the inner “l”.Kimberly Wright Cassidy - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):34-35.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Representational advantages.Roberto Casati - 2003 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 103 (3):281–298.
    Descriptive metaphysics investigates our naïve ontology as this is articulated in the content of our perception or of our pre-reflective thought about the world. But is access to such content reliable? Sceptics about the standard modes of access (introspection, or language-driven intuitions) may think that investigations in descriptive metaphysics can be aided by the controlled findings of cognitive science. Cognitive scientists have studied a promising range of representational advantages, that is, ways in which cognition favours one type of entity over (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Toward unified cognitive theory: The path is well worn and the trenches are deep.John M. Carroll - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):441-441.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The informational support for upright stance.Claudia Carello, M. T. Turvey & Peter N. Kugler - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):151-152.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Social-Cultural Processes and Urban Affordances for Healthy and Sustainable Food Consumption.Giuseppe Carrus, Sabine Pirchio & Stefano Mastandrea - 2018 - Frontiers in Psychology 9.
    In this paper, we provide an overview of research highlighting the relation between cultural processes, social norms, and food choices, discussing the implication of these findings for the promotion of more sustainable lifestyles. Our aim is to outline how environmental psychological research on urban affordances, through the specific concepts of restorative environments and walkability, could complement these findings to better understand human health, wellbeing and quality of life. We highlight how social norms and cultural processes are linked to food choices, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Reframing the problem of intelligent behavior.Stuart K. Card - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):438-439.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Précis of the origin of concepts.Susan Carey - 2011 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 34 (3):113-124.
    A theory of conceptual development must specify the innate representational primitives, must characterize the ways in which the initial state differs from the adult state, and must characterize the processes through which one is transformed into the other. The Origin of Concepts (henceforth TOOC) defends three theses. With respect to the initial state, the innate stock of primitives is not limited to sensory, perceptual, or sensorimotor representations; rather, there are also innate conceptual representations. With respect to developmental change, conceptual development (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • Navigating through a volumetric world does not imply needing a full three-dimensional representation.Claus-Christian Carbon & Vera M. Hesslinger - 2013 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36 (5):547-548.
    Jeffery et al. extensively and thoroughly describe how different species navigate through a three-dimensional environment. Undeniably, the world offers numerous three-dimensional opportunities. However, we argue that for most navigation tasks a two-dimensional representation is nevertheless sufficient, as physical conditions and limitations such as gravity, thermoclines, or layers of earth encountered in a specific situation provide the very elevation data the navigating individual needs.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is pictorial space “perceived” as real space?Josiane Caron-Pargue - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):75-76.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A unified theory for psychologists?Richard A. Carlson & Mark Detweiler - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):440-440.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What do attachment objects afford?John P. Capitanio - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):512-513.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Variations of reflex parameters and their implications for the control of movements.Charles Capaday & Richard B. Stein - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):600-602.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Pick your poison: Historicism, essentialism, and emergentism in the definition of species.Arthur L. Caplan - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):285-286.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • The Representation of Objects in Apraxia: From Action Execution to Error Awareness.Loredana Canzano, Michele Scandola, Valeria Gobbetto, Giuseppe Moretto, Daniela D’Imperio & Valentina Moro - 2016 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 10.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Knowing levels and the child's understanding of mind.Robert L. Campbell & Mark H. Bickhard - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):33-34.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • If human cognition is adaptive, can human knowledge consist of encodings?Robert L. Campbell & Mark H. Bickhard - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):488-489.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Educating Semiosis: Foundational Concepts for an Ecological Edusemiotic.Cary Campbell - 2018 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 38 (3):291-317.
    Many edusemiotic writers have begun to closely align edusemitoics to biosemiotics; the basic logic being that, if the life process can be defined through the criterion of semiotic engagement, so can the learning process :373–387, 2006). Thus, the ecological concept of umwelt has come to be a central area of investigation for edusemiotics; allowing theorists to address learning and living concurrently, from the perspective of meaning and significance. To address the conceptual and experiential foundations of the edusemiotic perspective, this paper (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Analysing real-world visual search tasks helps explain what the functional visual field is, and what its neural mechanisms are.John Campion - 2017 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 40:e133.
    Rejecting information-processing-based theory permits the merging of a top-down analysis of visual search tasks with a bottom-up analysis of brain structure and function. This reveals the true nature of the functional visual field and its precise role in the conduct of visual search tasks. The merits of such analyses over the traditional methods of the authors are described.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Beyond “Error-Correction”.Paco Calvo, John Symons & Emma Martín - 2012 - Frontiers in Psychology 3.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Nonconceptual apprehension and the reason-giving character of perception.Arnon Cahen - 2019 - Synthese 196 (6):2355-2383.
    I argue that the debate about the reason-giving character of perception, and, derivatively, the contemporary debate about the nature of the conceptual content of perception, is best viewed as a confrontation with refined versions of the following three independently plausible, yet mutually inconsistent, propositions: Perceptual apprehension Some perceptions provide reasons directly Exclusivity Only beliefs provide reasons directly Bifurcation No perception is a belief I begin with an evaluation and refinement of each proposition so as to crystallize the source of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Acting is perceiving!Rouwen Cañal-Bruland, John van der Kamp & Rob Gray - 2016 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 39.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Learning by imitation: A hierarchical approach.Richard W. Byrne & Anne E. Russon - 1998 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 21 (5):667-684.
    To explain social learning without invoking the cognitively complex concept of imitation, many learning mechanisms have been proposed. Borrowing an idea used routinely in cognitive psychology, we argue that most of these alternatives can be subsumed under a single process, priming, in which input increases the activation of stored internal representations. Imitation itself has generally been seen as a This has diverted much research towards the all-or-none question of whether an animal can imitate, with disappointingly inconclusive results. In the great (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • Hierarchical levels of imitation.R. W. Byrne - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):516-517.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation