Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Defending the four principles approach as a good basis for good medical practice and therefore for good medical ethics.Raanan Gillon - 2015 - Journal of Medical Ethics 41 (1):111-116.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Supererogation and the profession of medicine.A. C. McKay - 2002 - Journal of Medical Ethics 28 (2):70-73.
    In the light of increasing public mistrust, there is an urgent need to clarify the moral status of the medical profession and of the relationship of the clinician to his/her patients. In addressing this question, I first establish the coherence, within moral philosophy generally, of the concept of supererogation . I adopt the notion of an act of “unqualified” supererogation as one that is non-derivatively good, praiseworthy, and freely undertaken for others' benefit at the risk of some cost to the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Hippocratic Beneficence: The Ethical Grounding of Remedial Germline Editing.Eli Y. Adashi & I. Glenn Cohen - forthcoming - American Journal of Bioethics:1-3.
    Heritable monogenic maladies, the byproduct of single gene mutations, comprise a broad range of over 10,000 inborn afflictions (OMIM® 2023). Some of the more common monogenic disorders in question...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Commentary.R. Gillon - 2002 - Journal of Medical Ethics 28 (1):7-9.
    IN DEFENCE OF MEDICAL COMMITMENT CEREMONIESI confess to an overwhelming astonishment on first reading my friend Bob Veatch's attack on white coat ceremonies. Surely, I had thought, everyone who considered the issue would want doctors to commit themselves to the basic moral goals of medicine and especially that ancient Hippocratic goal of working to benefit the health of their/our patients, and only risking or doing harm with the intention and likely outcome of producing their net health benefit? Surely, too, it's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Supererogation and altruism: a comment.R. S. Downie - 2002 - Journal of Medical Ethics 28 (2):75-76.
    Supererogation can be distinguished from altruism, in that the former is located in the category of duty but exceeds the strict requirements of duty, whereas altruism belongs to a different moral category from duty. It follows that doctors do not act altruistically in their professional roles. Individual doctors may sometimes show supererogation, but supererogation is not a necessary feature of the medical profession. The aim of medicine is to act in the best interests of patients. This aim involves neither supererogation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Against the magnanimous in medical ethics.M. H. Kottow - 1990 - Journal of Medical Ethics 16 (3):124-128.
    Supererogatory acts are considered by some to be part of medicine, whereas others accept supererogation to be a gratuitous virtue, to be extolled when present, but not to be demanded. The present paper sides with those contending that medicine is duty-bound to benefit patients and that supererogation/altruism must per definition remain outside and beyond any role-description of the profession. Medical ethics should be bound by rational ethics and steer away from separatist views which grant exclusive privileges but also create excessive (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation