Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Self-Love and Altruism.David O. Brink - 1997 - Social Philosophy and Policy 14 (1):122-157.
    Whether morality has rational authority is an open question insofar as we can seriously entertain conceptions of morality and practical reason according to which it need not be contrary to reason to fail to conform to moral requirements. Doubts about the authority of morality are especially likely to arise for those who hold a broadly prudential view of rationality. It is common to think of morality as including various other-regarding duties of cooperation, forbearance, and aid. Most of us also regard (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Eudaimonism, Love and Friendship, and Political Community*: DAVID O. BRINK.David O. Brink - 1999 - Social Philosophy and Policy 16 (1):252-289.
    It is common to regard love, friendship, and other associational ties to others as an important part of a happy or flourishing life. This would be easy enough to understand if we focused on friendships based on pleasure, or associations, such as business partnerships, predicated on mutual advantage. For then we could understand in a straightforward way how these interpersonal relationships would be valuable for someone involved in such relationships just insofar as they caused her pleasure or causally promoted her (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Contra la arrogancia de Critias: ¿Parménides detrás del Cármides?Beatriz Bossi López - 2017 - Endoxa 39:31.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Meno, the Slave Boy and the Elenchos.Hugh H. Benson - 1990 - Phronesis 35 (1):128-158.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Wine and Catharsis_ of the Emotions in Plato's _Laws.Elizabeth Belfiore - 1986 - Classical Quarterly 36 (2):421-437.
    Plato's views on tragedy depend in large part on his views about the ethical consequences of emotional arousal. In theRepublic, Plato treats the desires we feel in everyday life to weep and feel pity as appetites exactly like those for food or sex, whose satisfactions are ‘replenishments’. Physical desire is not reprehensible in itself, but is simplynon-rational, not identical with reason but capable of being brought into agreement with it. Some desires, like that for simple and wholesome food, are in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Colloquium 7: Philosophy, Virtue, and Immortality in Plato’s Phaedo1.Jonathan Beere - 2011 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 26 (1):253-301.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Plato and Analytical Philosophy.Marcel Van Ackeren - 2005 - Erkenntnis 62 (2):263-275.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Plato on the Desire for the Good.Rachel Barney - 2010 - In Sergio Tenenbaum (ed.), Desire, Practical Reason, and the Good. Oxford University Press. pp. 34--64.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Aristotle's Ethics and the Crafts: A Critique.Thomas Peter Stephen Angier - unknown
    This dissertation is a study of the relation between Aristotle’s ethics and the crafts (or technai). My thesis is that Aristotle’s argument is at key points shaped by models proper to the crafts, this shaping being deeper than is generally acknowledged, and philosophically more problematic. Despite this, I conclude that the arguments I examine can, if revised, be upheld. The plan of the dissertation is as follows – Preface: The relation of my study to the extant secondary literature; Introduction: The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Socrates and Plato on Poetry.Nicholas D. Smith - 2007 - Philosophic Exchange 37 (1).
    This paper contrasts Socrates’ attitude towards poetry in the early dialogues with the sharply critical view of poetry expressed in Plato’s Republic. The difference between these two views constitutes further evidence for a developmentalist interpretation of Plato.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • اصول وجود- معرفت شناختي محاورات اوليه افلاطون.Mohammad Bagher Ghomi - 2015 - Hasti Va Shenakht 2 (1):37-54.
    در اين جستار بر آنيم اصول وجود شناختي و معرفت شناختي افلاطون در محاورات اوليه و علي الخصوص لاخس، خارميدس، اوثيفرون، اوتيدموس و هيپياس بزرگ را بر مبناي سه عنصر آنچه «دور سقراطي» مي ناميم يعني پرسش سقراطي، ادعاي سقراطي انكار دانش و النخوس مورد بررسي قرار دهيم. حاصل اين بررسي شش اصل وجود - معرفت شناختي است: شناخت الف، معرفت‌شناسي دوقطبي، وجودشناسي دو‌قطبي، معرفت گسسته، وجود گسسته و معرفت وجود. اگرچه اين اصول عمدتاً جديد نبوده و پيشتر مورد بحث (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Disputas por el método: ἔλεγχος y dialéctica en el Eutidemo de Platón.Hernán Inverso - 2014 - Circe de Clásicos y Modernos 18 (2):47-60.
    Platón delinea la filosofía como una disciplina que supera otros modos discursivos, como la poesía y la retórica, sugiriendo que deben ser transformados y orientados a criterios objetivistas con la dialéctica como parámetro en la cual tiene importancia central el mecanismo de la refutación. El presente trabajo se propone examinar este punto en el Eutidemo, prestando atención a la figura de Marsias para describir a Sócrates e identificar rasgos de la metodología platónica, y, sobre esta base, elucidar la relación entre (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Desire and reason in Plato's Republic.Hendrik Lorenz - 2004 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 27:83-116.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Two Dogmas of Platonism.Debra Nails - 2013 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 28 (1):77-112.
    Contemporary platonism has been conditioned in large part by two dogmas. One is the belief in a fundamental cleavage between intelligible but invisible Platonic forms that are real and eternal, and perceptible objects whose confinement to spacetime constitutes an inferior existence and about which knowledge is impossible. The other dogma involves a kind of reductionism: the belief that Plato’s unhypothetical first principle of the all is identical to the form of the good. Both dogmas, I argue, are ill-founded.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations