Switch to: References

Citations of:

Ontogeny and Phylogeny

Science and Society 43 (1):104-106 (1979)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Functional aspects of play as revealed by structural components and social interaction patterns.Marc Bekoff - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):156-157.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Testing the immunoreactive theory.William W. Beatty, Patricia A. Beatty & Donald E. Goodkin - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (3):442-442.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the separation of reproduction from mating preferences.Betty M. Bayer - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):92-93.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Linking the biological functions and the mechanisms of learning: Uses and abuses.Patrick Bateson - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):142-142.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Waddington’s Legacy to Developmental and Theoretical Biology.Jonathan B. L. Bard - 2008 - Biological Theory 3 (3):188-197.
    Conrad Hal Waddington was a British developmental biologist who mainly worked in Cambridge and Edinburgh, but spent the late 1930s with Morgan in California learning about Drosophila. He was the first person to realize that development depended on the then unknown activities of genes, and he needed an appropriate model organism. His major experimental contributions were to show how mutation analysis could be used to investigate developmental mechanisms in Drosophila, and to explore how developmental mutation could drive evolution, his other (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Understanding self and other.John Barresi & Chris Moore - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (1):142-154.
    We consider the various criticisms and requests for clarification made by the commentators of our framework for understanding intentional relations. Our response is organized according to the main themes in the target article: general theory, phylogeny, development, and autism. We also add some discussion of further issues, such as simulation and moral theory, that were not addressed in the target article.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The logical relation between cultural and biological evolution: On to the next question.Jerome H. Barkow - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):235-236.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Skinner on selection – A case study of intellectual isolation.George W. Barlow - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):481-482.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On the Origin of Language.Marcello Barbieri - 2010 - Biosemiotics 3 (2):201-223.
    Thomas Sebeok and Noam Chomsky are the acknowledged founding fathers of two research fields which are known respectively as Biosemiotics and Biolinguistics and which have been developed in parallel during the past 50 years. Both fields claim that language has biological roots and must be studied as a natural phenomenon, thus bringing to an end the old divide between nature and culture. In addition to this common goal, there are many other important similarities between them. Their definitions of language, for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Of false dichotomies and larger frames.Jerome H. Barkow - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):680-681.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Origin and Evolution of the Brain.Marcello Barbieri - 2011 - Biosemiotics 4 (3):369-399.
    Modern biology has not yet come to terms with the presence of many organic codes in Nature, despite the fact that we can prove their existence. As a result, it has not yet accepted the idea that the great events of macroevolution were associated with the origin of new organic codes, despite the fact that this is the most parsimonious and logical explanation of those events. This is probably due to the fact that the existence of organic codes in all (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Kuhnian revolutions in developmental biology.Jonathan Bard - 1996 - Bioessays 18 (11):937-937.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Intentional relations and social understanding.John Barresi & Chris Moore - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (1):107-122.
    Organisms engage in various activities that are directed at objects, whether real or imagined. Such activities may be termed “intentional relations.” We present a four-level framework of social understanding that organizes the ways in which social organisms represent the intentional relations of themselves and other agents. We presuppose that the information available to an organism about its own intentional relations (or first person information) is qualitatively different from the information available to that organism about other agents’ intentional relations (or third (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   73 citations  
  • From genes to mind to culture: Biting the bullet at last.David P. Barash - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):7-8.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Contingencies of selection, reinforcement, and survival.David P. Barash - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):680-680.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Can children with autism integrate first and third person representations?Simon Baron-Cohen - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (1):123-124.
    Barresi & Moore contrast two theories of autism: (1) in autism there is a general inability to integrate first and third person information (of any kind), and (2) in autism there is a specific inability to represent an agent's perceptual or volitional mental state being about another agents mental state. Two lines of experimental evidence suggest that the first of these is too broad, favoring instead the more specific “theory of mind” account.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A theory of learning - not even déjà vu.George W. Barlow & Stephen E. Glickman - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):141-142.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Control of developmental timing by small temporal RNAs: a paradigm for RNA‐mediated regulation of gene expression.Diya Banerjee & Frank Slack - 2002 - Bioessays 24 (2):119-129.
    Heterochronic genes control the timing of developmental programs. In C. elegans, two key genes in the heterochronic pathway, lin-4 and let-7, encode small temporally expressed RNAs (stRNAs) that are not translated into protein. These stRNAs exert negative post-transcriptional regulation by binding to complementary sequences in the 3′ untranslated regions of their target genes. stRNAs are transcribed as longer precursor RNAs that are processed by the RNase Dicer/DCR-1 and members of the RDE-1/AGO1 family of proteins, which are better known for their (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The nature-nurture error again.John D. Baldwin - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):155-156.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Pere Alberch’s Developmental Morphospaces and the Evolution of Cognition.Sergio Balari & Guillermo Lorenzo - 2008 - Biological Theory 3 (4):297-304.
    In this article we argue for an extension of Pere Alberch’s notion of developmental morphospace into the realm of cognition and introduce the notion of cognitive phenotype as a new tool for the evolutionary and developmental study of cognitive abilities.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Ontogenetic or phylogenetic – another afterpain of the fallacious Cartesian dichotomy.Gerard P. Baerends - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):679-680.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Conclusions from color vision of insects.Werner Backhaus & Randolf Menzel - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):28-30.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • A limited objectivism defended.Edward Wilson Averill - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):27-28.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Conceptual issues in the reunion of development and evolution.J. W. Atkinson - 1992 - Synthese 91 (1-2):93 - 110.
    Recently a growing number of biologists have begun to consider the causal role that processes of embryonic development may play in evolution. This constitutes a reunion of these phenomena which had been linked in the nineteenth century through Haeckel's biogenetic law. This reunion may result in a new subdiscipline of biology, if there is a set of unique concepts and methods which tie the various research approaches together. Such concepts as bauplan, canalization, and developmental constraint, may serve in such a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Conservative aspects of the dolphin cortex match its behavioral level.Lester R. Aronson & Ethel Tobach - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):89-90.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Traversing birth: continuity and contingency in research on development in nineteenth-century life and human sciences.Caroline Arni - 2015 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 37 (1):50-67.
    In the history of life sciences, it has often been argued that the individual organism emerged, around 1800, as a four-dimensional entity—a temporalized entity. Against this backdrop, the article asks how research on development contributed to structuring the time of the organism in terms of a historical process, that is, by understanding a given phenomenon as brought forth by what preceded it and as establishing conditions for what will follow, thus relating the past, the present and the future in a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Beyond Darwinism’s Eclipse: Functional Evolution, Biochemical Recapitulation and Spencerian Emergence in the 1920s and 1930s. [REVIEW]Rony Armon - 2010 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 41 (1):173 - 194.
    During the 1920s and 1930s, many biologists questioned the viability of Darwin’s theory as a mechanism of evolutionary change. In the early 1940s, and only after a number of alternatives were suggested, Darwinists succeeded to establish natural selection and gene mutation as the main evolutionary mechanisms. While that move, today known as the neo-Darwinian synthesis, is taken as signalling a triumph of evolutionary theory, certain critical problems in evolution—in particular the evolution of animal function—could not be addressed with this approach. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Beyond Darwinism’s Eclipse: Functional Evolution, Biochemical Recapitulation and Spencerian Emergence in the 1920s and 1930s.Rony Armon - 2010 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 41 (1):173-194.
    During the 1920s and 1930s, many biologists questioned the viability of Darwin’s theory as a mechanism of evolutionary change. In the early 1940s, and only after a number of alternatives were suggested, Darwinists succeeded to establish natural selection and gene mutation as the main evolutionary mechanisms. While that move, today known as the neo-Darwinian synthesis, is taken as signalling a triumph of evolutionary theory, certain critical problems in evolution—in particular the evolution of animal function—could not be addressed with this approach. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Jeffries Wyman, philosophical anatomy, and the scientific reception of Darwin in America.Toby A. Appel - 1988 - Journal of the History of Biology 21 (1):69-94.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Making the best use of primate tool use?James R. Anderson - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):551-552.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Classification of afferents by input not by output?P. L. R. Andrews & I. N. C. Lawes - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (2):300-301.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Skinner's circus.Stuart A. Altmann - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):678-679.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Samuel Butler's Contributions to Biological Philosophy.Barry Allen - 2023 - Common Knowledge 29 (2):251-279.
    Samuel Butler is usually remembered for Erewhon, widely considered among the best English satires. He also contributed to philosophical biology in works that collectively compose the nineteenth century's finest statement of the evolutionary argument associated with the name of Lamarck. In writing on evolution, Butler was not presenting science for a popular audience but deliberately intervening in the scientific argument about Darwinism. Surprised by the success of his first venture in philosophical biology, Life and Habit, Butler committed himself to the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Principles of learning and the ecological style of inquiry.Thomas R. Alley & Robert E. Shaw - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):139-141.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Perceived age, physical attractiveness and sex differences in preferred mates' ages.Thomas R. Alley - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):92-92.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Invertebrate Paleontology and Evolutionary Thinking in the US and Britain, 1860–1940.Warren D. Allmon - 2020 - Journal of the History of Biology 53 (3):423-450.
    The role of paleontology in evolutionary biology between the publication of The Origin of Species in 1859 and the Evolutionary Synthesis of the 1940s is frequently described as mostly misguided failure. However, a significant number of American and British PDPS invertebrate paleontologists of this period did devote considerable attention to evolution, and their evolutionary theories and conclusions were a good deal more diverse and nuanced than previous histories have suggested. This paper brings into focus a number of important but underrecognized (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Comparative cognitive studies, not folk phylogeny, please.Colin Allen - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (1):122-123.
    Barresi & Moore (B&M) provide a useful tool for the comparative study of social cognition that could, however, be improved by more subtle analysis of first person information about intentional relations. Knowledge of misrepresentation also needs to be better handled within the theory. I urge skepticism about B&M's sweeping phylogenetic claims.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A return to the Bauplan.Pere Alberch - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (3):332-332.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reflections on the Middle Stages of EvoDevo’s Ontogeny.Alan C. Love - 2006 - Biological Theory 1 (1):94-97.
    Evolutionary developmental biology (or developmental evolution) is in the middle stages of its “development.” Its early ontogeny cannot be traced back to fertilization but pivotal developmental events included Gould’s (1977) treatment of heterochrony, Riedl’s (1978) analysis of “burden”, the Dahlem conference of 1981, a British Society of Developmental Biologists Symposium, as well as books that incorporated developmental genetics into older comparative themes. A major inductive process began with the discovery of widespread phylogenetic conservation in homeobox-containing genes. One interpretation of these (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • More than mere coloring: The art of spectral vision.Kathleen A. Akins & John Lamping - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):26-27.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The tragedy of a priori selectionism: Dennett and Gould on adaptationism. [REVIEW]Jeremy C. Ahouse - 1998 - Biology and Philosophy 13 (3):359-391.
    In his recent book on Darwinism, Daniel Dennett has offered up a species of a priori selectionism that he calls algorithmic. He used this view to challenge a number of positions advocated by Stephen J. Gould. I examine his algorithmic conception, review his unqualified enthusiasm for the a priori selectionist position, challenge Dennett's main metaphors (cranes vs. skyhooks and a design space), examine ways in which his position has lead him to misunderstand or misrepresent Gould (spandrels, exaptation, punctuated equilibrium, contingency (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Immunoselection and male diseases.Matteo Adinolfi - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (3):441-442.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Behavior, body types and the irreversibility of evolution.Francisco Aboitiz - 1990 - Acta Biotheoretica 38 (2):91-101.
    A functional approach to evolutionary morphology is emphasized in this paper. This perspective differs from the current structuralist trend, which emphasizes the constraining role of developmental paths. In addition, the present approach agrees with the adaptationist paradigm. It is further argued that three types of phenomena are better understood in this light: i.- the existence of evolutionary trends, ii.- the maintenance of certain structural features within a given taxon, and iii.- the irreversibility of evolution.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Material conditions and human freedom.Enzo Rossi, Annelien de Dijn, Grant McCall, David Wengrow & Karl Widerquist - forthcoming - Contemporary Political Theory.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The problem of form in molecular biology.Laura Nuño de la Rosa & Fernando M. Pérez Herranz - 2009 - In José Luis González Recio (ed.), Philosophical essays on physics and biology. New York: G. Olms.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Denis Dutton, The Art Instinct. New York: Oxford University Press 2009. Pp. 278.Mohan Matthen - 2011 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 41 (2):337-356.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dynamic Oppositional Symmetries for Color, Jungian and Kantian Categories.Julio Michael Stern - manuscript
    This paper investigates some classical oppositional categories, like synthetic vs. analytic, posterior vs. prior, imagination vs. grammar, metaphor vs. hermeneutics, metaphysics vs. observation, innovation vs. routine, and image vs. sound, and the role they play in epistemology and philosophy of science. The epistemological framework of objective cognitive constructivism is of special interest in these investigations. Oppositional relations are formally represented using algebraic lattice structures like the cube and the hexagon of opposition, with applications in the contexts of modern color theory, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Communication: Where Evolutionary Linguistics Went Wrong.Guillermo Lorenzo & Sergio Balari - 2010 - Biological Theory 5 (3):228-239.
    In this article we offer a detailed assessment of current approaches to the origins of language, with a special foots on their historical and theoretical underpinnings. It is a widely accepted view within evolutionary linguistics that an account of the emergence of human language necessarily involves paying special attention to its communicative function and its relation to other animal communication systems. Ever since Darwin, some variant of this view has constituted the mainstream version in evolutionary linguistics; however, it is our (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Entangled Life: Organism and Environment in the Biological and Social Sciences.Gillian Barker, Eric Desjardins & Trevor Pearce (eds.) - 2014 - Dordrecht: Springer.
    Despite the burgeoning interest in new and more complex accounts of the organism-environment dyad by biologists and philosophers, little attention has been paid in the resulting discussions to the history of these ideas and to their deployment in disciplines outside biology—especially in the social sciences. Even in biology and philosophy, there is a lack of detailed conceptual models of the organism-environment relationship. This volume is designed to fill these lacunae by providing the first multidisciplinary discussion of the topic of organism-environment (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Tricks of Transference: Oka Asajirō (1868–1944) on Laissez-faire Capitalism.Gregory Sullivan - 2010 - Science in Context 23 (3):367-391.
    ArgumentContrary to common portrayals of social Darwinism as a transference of laissez-faire values, the widely read evolutionism of Japan's foremost Darwinist of the early twentieth-century, Oka Asajirō (1868–1944), reflects a statist outlook that regards capitalism as the beginning of the nation's degeneration. The evolutionary theory of orthogenesis that Oka employed in his 1910 essay, “The Future of Humankind,” links him to a pre-Darwinian idealist tradition that depicted the state as an organism that develops through life-cycle stages. For Oka, laissez-faire capitalism (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark