Switch to: References

Citations of:

Plato: The Collected Dialogues

Princeton: New Jersey: Princeton University Press (1961)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. (1 other version)Understanding the Role of the Laws in Plato's "Statesman".Sandrine Berges - 2010 - Prolegomena 9 (1):5-23.
    In the Statesman, Plato seems to be advocating that in the absence of a true king who will rule independently of laws, the next best thing as far as just rule is concerned is to ad here rigidly to existing laws, whatever they are. The rule of the true king is given as an example of virtuous rule in the sense that virtue politics or jurisprudence holds that laws cannot always deal justly with particular cases. But Plato’s view of what (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Challenge of Ethical Relativism in a Coalition Environment.David Whetham - 2008 - Journal of Military Ethics 7 (4):302-316.
    It appears fairly obvious that different cultures look at things in different ways. In Book III of his History, Herodotus gives an excellent and well-known example of ethical relativism by explaini...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Dialectic and diagonalization.John Kadvany - 1991 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 34 (1):3 – 25.
    This essay is about mathematics as a written or literate language. Through historical and anthropological observations drawn from the history of Greek mathematics and the oral tradition preceding the rise of literacy in Greece, as well as considerations on the nature of alphabetic writing, it is argued that three essential linguistic features of mathematical discourse are jointly possible only through written, alphabetic language. The essay concludes with a discussion of how both alphabetic principles and issues related to literacy faced by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Epinomia: Plato and the First Legal Theory.Eric Heinze - 2007 - Ratio Juris 20 (1):97-135.
    In comparison to Aristotle, Plato's general understanding of law receives little attention in legal theory, due in part to ongoing perceptions of him as a mystic or a totalitarian. However, some of the critical or communitarian themes that have guided theorists since Aristotle find strong expression in Plato's work. More than any thinker until the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, Plato rejects the rank individualism and self-interest which, in his view, emerge from democratic legal culture. He rejects schisms between legal norms (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Varieties of goodness in the school curriculum.David Carr - 1993 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 25 (1):1–18.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Epistemic Collaborativeness as an Intellectual Virtue.Alkis Kotsonis - 2023 - Erkenntnis 88 (3):869-884.
    Despite the recent growth of studies in virtue epistemology, the intellectual virtue of epistemic collaborativeness has been overlooked by scholars working in virtue theory. This is a significant gap in the literature given the import of well-motivated and skillful epistemic collaboration for the flourishing of human societies. This paper engages in an in-depth examination of the intellectual virtue of epistemic collaborativeness. It argues that the agent who possesses this acquired character trait is (i) highly motivated to engage in epistemic collaboration (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Division of Labor in Vocabulary Structure: Insights From Corpus Analyses.Morten H. Christiansen & Padraic Monaghan - 2016 - Topics in Cognitive Science 8 (3):610-624.
    Psychologists have used experimental methods to study language for more than a century. However, only with the recent availability of large-scale linguistic databases has a more complete picture begun to emerge of how language is actually used, and what information is available as input to language acquisition. Analyses of such “big data” have resulted in reappraisals of key assumptions about the nature of language. As an example, we focus on corpus-based research that has shed new light on the arbitrariness of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Tragedy of Platonic Ethics and the Fall of Socrates.Wendy C. Hamblet - 2003 - Ethic@ - An International Journal for Moral Philosophy 2 (2):137–150.
    This paper considers the use of myth in the Platonic dialogues. It seeks to demonstrate that Plato takesup the task of rewriting the old myths, not in order to clarify the real truth about ancient tales, but to make thosetales serve higher—ethical—ends. Thus Plato makes a valiant effort to replace the old "truths" in order to displaceand overcome ethically dangerous assumptions in the old tales. But I shall demonstrate that, despite the changesin mythical content, the old tropes endure in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Implicit and explicit memory models.Henry L. Roediger - 1979 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 13 (6):339-342.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Hegel and the Consequentia Mirabilis.Elena Ficara - 2018 - History and Philosophy of Logic 39 (4):357-364.
    In this paper I argue that Hegel’s treatment of dialectical inferences, in particular of Plato’s dialectics in the Lectures on the History of Philosophy, belongs to the history of the logical rule that, from Gerolamo Cardano to Bertrand Russell, is known as consequentia mirabilis. In 1906 Russell formalises it as follows: and its correspondent positive form as My paper has two parts. First, I show that dialectical inferences, for Hegel, involve sentences of the form and. Hegel, following Plato, stresses that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Revisiting the liberal and vocational dimensions of university education.David Carr - 2009 - British Journal of Educational Studies 57 (1):1-17.
    The purposes of higher education in general and of university education in particular have long been subject to controversy. Whereas for some, the main role of universities is to provide professional and vocational education and training and their benefits are to be measured in terms of social or economic utility, their value for others is to be seen more in terms of the liberal development and promotion of certain intrinsically worthwhile qualities of mind and intellect. In this context, indeed, much (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • (1 other version)Was Socrates the first philosophical practitioner, the first psychologist, or both?Chet Sunde - 2005 - Philosophical Practice 1 (2):73-74.
    (2005). Was Socrates the first philosophical practitioner, the first psychologist, or both? Philosophical Practice: Vol. 1, No. 2, pp. 73-74.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Was Socrates the first philosophical practitioner, the first psychologist, or both?Chet Sunde - 2005 - Philosophical Practice: Journal of the American Philosophical Practitioners Association 1 (2):73-74.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • “Loving Nature” Nature's Way: Exploring Radical Participation With Nature Through the Metaphor of Complex, Dynamic Self-Systems.Regula Wegmann - 2012 - World Futures 68 (2):82 - 92.
    The Western metaphor of self-as-identity?as a static, inherently exclusive entity?has been instrumental, historically, to our radical separation from nature, and still hampers a reviving of genuine participation with nature. Suggesting an alternative to this metaphor (informed by literacy as technology), I explore the more nature-informed metaphor of dynamic, complex self-systems, involving both natural and human subsystems. Through this latter metaphor, I re-vision radical participation with nature: in the process of perception, in epistemology/ontology, and in the ways of indigenous, oral cultures. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Is this a world where knowledge has to include justification?Stephen Hetherington - 2007 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 75 (1):41–69.
    If any thesis is all-but-universally accepted by contemporary epistemologists, it is justificationism-the thesis that being an instance of knowledge has to include being epistemically justified in some appropriate way. If there is to be any epistemological knowledge about knowledge, a paradigm candidate would seem to be our knowledge that justificationism is true. This is a conception of a way in whichknowledge has to be robust. Nevertheless, this paper provides reason to doubt the truth of that conception. Even epistemology’s supposed conceptual (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Can compassion be taught?G. E. Pence - 1983 - Journal of Medical Ethics 9 (4):189-191.
    Socrates (in the Meno) denied that virtues like courage could be taught, whereas Protagoras defended this claim. Compassion is discussed below in this context; it is distinguished from related, but different, moral qualities, and the role of imagination is emphasised. 'Sympathy's and role-modelling views of compassion's acquisition are criticised. Compassion can indeed be taught, but neither by the example of a few, isolated physicians nor by creation of Departments of Compassion. In replying to one standard objection to teaching compassion, it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Characterisation and Interpretation: The Importance of Drama in Plato's Sophist.Eugenio Benitez - 1996 - Literature & Aesthetics 6:27-39.
    Plato's Sophist is complex. Its themes are many and ambiguous. The early grammarians gave it the subtitle1tEp1. 'tau ov'to~ ('on being') and assigned it to Plato's logical investigations. The Neoplatonists prized it for a theory of ontological categories they preferred to Aristotle's. Modern scholars sometimes court paradox and refer to the Sophist as Plato's dialogue on not-being (because the question ofthe possibility of not-being occupies much of the dialogue). Whitehead took the Sophist to be primarily about ouvo.~t~ ('power') and found (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Can Educationally Significant Learning be Assessed?Steven A. Stolz - 2017 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 49 (4).
    This article argues that assessment is a central feature of teaching, particularly as a means to determine whether what has been taught has been learnt. However, I take issue with the current trend in education which places a significant amount of emphasis upon large-scale public testing, which in turn has exacerbated the ‘teaching-to-the-test’ syndrome, not to mention distorting teaching decisions that are detrimental to the overall development of student knowledge and understanding. Part of the problem with assessment in education seems (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Virtue as Mental Health: A Platonic Defence of the Medical Model in Ethics.Sandrine Berges - 2012 - Journal of Ancient Philosophy 6 (1).
    I argue that Plato holds a medical model of virtue as health which does not have themorally unacceptable implications which have led some to describe it as authoritarian.This model, which draws on the educational virtues of the elenchos, lacks anyimplication that all criminals are mad or all mad people criminals – this implication beingat the source of many criticisms of Plato’s analogy of virtue and health. After setting upthe analogy and the model, I defend my argument against two objections. The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations