Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. What's Aristotelian about neo‐Aristotelian Virtue Ethics?Sukaina Hirji - 2019 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 98 (3):671-696.
    It is commonly assumed that Aristotle's ethical theory shares deep structural similarities with neo-Aristotelian virtue ethics. I argue that this assumption is a mistake, and that Aristotle's ethical theory is both importantly distinct from the theories his work has inspired, and independently compelling. I take neo-Aristotelian virtue ethics to be characterized by two central commitments: (i) virtues of character are defined as traits that reliably promote an agent's own flourishing, and (ii) virtuous actions are defined as the sorts of actions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Normative stakeholder theory and Aristotle: The link between ethics and politics. [REVIEW]Nachoem M. Wijnberg - 2000 - Journal of Business Ethics 25 (4):329 - 342.
    Stakeholder theory is an important part of modern business ethics. Many scholars argue for a normative instead of an instrumental approach to stakeholder theory. Recent examples of such an approach show that problems appear with respect to the ethical foundation as well as the specification of the norms and the relation between corporate and individual responsibilities. This paper argues for the relevance of Aristotle's ideas on ethics and politics, and especially the link between them, for stakeholder theory. An Aristotelian approach (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Une formulation néo-aristotélicienne de la doctrine du juste milieu.Paul Franceschi - manuscript
    Dans cet article, nous présentons une formulation néo-aristotélicienne de la doctrine du juste milieu. Nous commençons par décrire la formulation classique de la doctrine par Aristote, telle qu'elle est exposée dans l’Éthique à Nicomaque. Nous présentons en outre les éléments fondamentaux qui régissent les matrices de concepts (Franceschi 2002). Nous proposons ensuite une nouvelle formulation de la doctrine du juste milieu, directement dérivée de la structure-même des matrices de concepts. Nous comparons également la présente formulation de la doctrine du juste (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Defending the Doctrine of the Mean Against Counterexamples: A General Strategy.Nicholas Colgrove - 2024 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly (Online First):1-24.
    Aristotle’s doctrine of the mean states that each moral virtue stands opposed to two types of vice: one of excess and one of deficiency, respectively. Critics claim that some virtues—like honesty, fair-mindedness, and patience—are counterexamples to Aristotle’s doctrine. Here, I develop a generalizable strategy to defend the doctrine of the mean against such counterexamples. I argue that not only is the doctrine of the mean defensible, but taking it seriously also allows us to gain substantial insight into particular virtues. Failure (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Understanding Aristotle's Notion of the Mean: A Case Study in Anger.Heather Stewart - 2019 - Labyrinth: An International Journal for Philosophy, Value Theory and Sociocultural Hermeneutics 21 (1):139-155.
    In this paper, I argue that purely quantitative understandings of Aristotle's concept of "the mean" are oversimplified, and I make this argument by analyzing the particular emotion of anger. Anger, I contend, helps to complicate the purely quantitative understanding of the mean, insofar as, I argue, the amount of anger experienced is not the morally salient feature in determining whether or not the anger is virtuous. Rather, anger is one example of an emotion or trait for which other, non-quantitative parameters (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • La vertu morale aristotélicienne en tant que médiété pros hemas : perspectives quantitative et relativiste.Louise Rodrigue - 2013 - Philosophie Antique 13:243-264.
    Cette étude porte sur la notion aristotélicienne de vertu morale dans son sens strict, c’est‑à‑dire entendue comme médiété fixée relativement à nous. L’analyse et la critique des interprétations dites « quantitatives » d’une part, « relativistes » d’autre part, résultent en une clarification de la définition donnée par les Éthiques (cf. 1106b36‑1107a6 et 1227b8-9).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Virtue ethics and anti-theory.Robert B. Louden - 1990 - Philosophia 20 (1-2):93-114.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Nature of Moral Virtue.Erik Joseph Wielenberg - 2000 - Dissertation, University of Massachusetts Amherst
    The dissertation is centered around the Moral Virtuosity Project . The central task of the dissertation is to examine what other philosophers have had to say on this topic and ultimately to successfully complete this project. ;Chapter One is concerned exclusively with Aristotle's attempt to complete the Moral Virtuosity Project. I defend the view that Aristotle holds that each moral virtue is a disposition toward proper practical reasoning, action, and emotion within a certain sphere. I critically examine Aristotle's argument for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)An Ingenuous Account of the Doctrine of the Mean.Christopher Martin - 1994 - Tópicos: Revista de Filosofía 6 (1):31-57.
    Aristóteles admite la posibilidad de que muchos vicios se opongan a una virtud, pero insiste en que siempre hay al menos dos, relacionados con la deficiencia y el exceso. Así, la doctrina de que la virtud está en el medio es tanto verdadera como útil.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Wisdom, Piety, and Superhuman Virtue.Daniel Frank - 2019 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 36 (3):199-216.
    This article moves between Aristotle, Maimonides, and the Stoics. Aristotle’s moral taxonomy, outlined in NE 7.1, appears problematic, given his view that, in the sphere of moral virtue, the intermediate (temperance, courage) is the extreme, and there is no excess of temperance or courage. This is hard to square with the moral agent whom he describes as possessed of “hyperbolic” (hyperbole, excessive) virtue. As Aristotle has very little to say about the latter, I turn to Maimonides and the Stoics for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark