Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Indecomposability of negative dense subsets of ℝ in Constructive Reverse Mathematics.Iris Loeb - 2009 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 17 (2):173-177.
    In 1970 Vesley proposed a substitute of Kripke's Scheme. In this paper it is shown that —over Bishop's constructive mathematics— the indecomposability of negative dense subsets of ℝ is equivalent to a weakening of Vesley's proposal. This result supports the idea that full Kripke's Scheme might not be necessary for most of intuitionistic mathematics. At the same time it contributes to the programme of Constructive Reverse Mathematics and gives a new answer to a 1997 question of Van Dalen.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Intuitionistic notions of boundedness in ℕ.Fred Richman - 2009 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 55 (1):31-36.
    We consider notions of boundedness of subsets of the natural numbers ℕ that occur when doing mathematics in the context of intuitionistic logic. We obtain a new characterization of the notion of a pseudobounded subset and we formulate the closely related notion of a detachably finite subset. We establish metric equivalents for a subset of ℕ to be detachably finite and to satisfy the ascending chain condition. Following Ishihara, we spell out the relationship between detachable finiteness and sequential continuity. Most (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Constructive mathematics.Douglas Bridges - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Glueing continuous functions constructively.Douglas S. Bridges & Iris Loeb - 2010 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 49 (5):603-616.
    The glueing of (sequentially, pointwise, or uniformly) continuous functions that coincide on the intersection of their closed domains is examined in the light of Bishop-style constructive analysis. This requires us to pay attention to the way that the two domains intersect.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The uniform boundedness theorem and a boundedness principle.Hajime Ishihara - 2012 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 163 (8):1057-1061.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (2 other versions)Arguments for the Continuity Principle. [REVIEW]Mark van Atten & Dirk van Dalen - 2002 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 8 (3):329-347.
    There are two principles that lend Brouwer's mathematics the extra power beyond arithmetic. Both are presented in Brouwer's writings with little or no argument. One, the principle of bar induction, will not concern us here. The other, the continuity principle for numbers, occurs for the first time in print in [4]. It is formulated and immediately applied to show that the set of numerical choice sequences is not enumerable. In fact, the idea of the continuity property can be dated fairly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (2 other versions)Arguments for the Continuity Principle.Mark Van Atten & Dirk Van Dalen - 2002 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 8 (3):329 - 347.
    There are two principles that lend Brouwer's mathematics the extra power beyond arithmetic. Both are presented in Brouwer's writings with little or no argument. One, the principle of bar induction, will not concern us here. The other, the continuity principle for numbers, occurs for the first time in print in [4]. It is formulated and immediately applied to show that the set of numerical choice sequences is not enumerable. In fact, the idea of the continuity property can be dated fairly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (2 other versions)Arguments for the continuity principle.Mark van Atten & Dirk van Dalen - 2002 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 8 (3):329-347.
    There are two principles that lend Brouwer's mathematics the extra power beyond arithmetic. Both are presented in Brouwer's writings with little or no argument. One, the principle of bar induction, will not concern us here. The other, the continuity principle for numbers, occurs for the first time in print in [4]. It is formulated and immediately applied to show that the set of numerical choice sequences is not enumerable. In fact, the idea of the continuity property can be dated fairly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Strong continuity implies uniform sequential continuity.Douglas Bridges, Hajime Ishihara, Peter Schuster & Luminiţa Vîţa - 2005 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 44 (7):887-895.
    Uniform sequential continuity, a property classically equivalent to sequential continuity on compact sets, is shown, constructively, to be a consequence of strong continuity on a metric space. It is then shown that in the case of a separable metric space, uniform sequential continuity implies strong continuity if and only if one adopts a certain boundedness principle that, although valid in the classical, recursive and intuitionistic setting, is independent of Heyting arithmetic.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The Banach‐Steinhaus theorem for the space ????(ℝ) in constructive analysis.Satoru Yoshida - 2003 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 49 (3):305-315.
    We prove the Banach‐Steinhaus theorem for distributions on the space ????(ℝ) within Bishop's constructive mathematics. To this end, we investigate the constructive sequential completion $ \tilde {\cal D} $(ℝ) of ????(ℝ).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Unique solutions.Peter Schuster - 2006 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 52 (6):534-539.
    It is folklore that if a continuous function on a complete metric space has approximate roots and in a uniform manner at most one root, then it actually has a root, which of course is uniquely determined. Also in Bishop's constructive mathematics with countable choice, the general setting of the present note, there is a simple method to validate this heuristic principle. The unique solution even becomes a continuous function in the parameters by a mild modification of the uniqueness hypothesis. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Realizability models refuting Ishiharaʼs boundedness principle.Peter Lietz & Thomas Streicher - 2012 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 163 (12):1803-1807.
    Ishiharaʼs boundedness principleBD-N was introduced in Ishihara [5] and has turned out to be most useful for constructive analysis, see e.g. Ishihara [6]. It is equivalent to the statement that every sequentially continuous function from NN to N is continuous w.r.t. the usual metric topology on NN. We construct models for higher order arithmetic and intuitionistic set theory in which both every function from NN to N is sequentially continuous and in which the axiom of choice from NN to N (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Coding of real‐valued continuous functions under WKL$\mathsf {WKL}$.Tatsuji Kawai - 2023 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 69 (3):370-391.
    In the context of constructive reverse mathematics, we show that weak Kőnig's lemma () implies that every pointwise continuous function is induced by a code in the sense of reverse mathematics. This, combined with the fact that implies the Fan theorem, shows that implies the uniform continuity theorem: every pointwise continuous function has a modulus of uniform continuity. Our results are obtained in Heyting arithmetic in all finite types with quantifier‐free axiom of choice.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Uniform Continuity Properties of Preference Relations.Douglas S. Bridges - 2008 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 49 (1):97-106.
    The anti-Specker property, a constructive version of sequential compactness, is used to prove constructively that a pointwise continuous, order-dense preference relation on a compact metric space is uniformly sequentially continuous. It is then shown that Ishihara's principle BD-ℕ implies that a uniformly sequentially continuous, order-dense preference relation on a separable metric space is uniformly continuous. Converses of these two theorems are also proved.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The anti-Specker property, positivity, and total boundedness.Douglas Bridges & Hannes Diener - 2010 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 56 (4):434-441.
    Working within Bishop-style constructive mathematics, we examine some of the consequences of the anti-Specker property, known to be equivalent to a version of Brouwer's fan theorem. The work is a contribution to constructive reverse mathematics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Continuity properties of preference relations.Marian A. Baroni & Douglas S. Bridges - 2008 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 54 (5):454-459.
    Various types of continuity for preference relations on a metric space are examined constructively. In particular, necessary and sufficient conditions are given for an order-dense, strongly extensional preference relation on a complete metric space to be continuous. It is also shown, in the spirit of constructive reverse mathematics, that the continuity of sequentially continuous, order-dense preference relations on complete, separable metric spaces is connected to Ishihara's principleBD-ℕ, and therefore is not provable within Bishop-style constructive mathematics alone.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Constructive aspects of Riemann’s permutation theorem for series.J. Berger, Douglas Bridges, Hannes Diener & Helmet Schwichtenberg - forthcoming - Logic Journal of the IGPL.
    The notions of permutable and weak-permutable convergence of a series|$\sum _{n=1}^{\infty }a_{n}$|of real numbers are introduced. Classically, these two notions are equivalent, and, by Riemann’s two main theorems on the convergence of series, a convergent series is permutably convergent if and only if it is absolutely convergent. Working within Bishop-style constructive mathematics, we prove that Ishihara’s principle BD-|$\mathbb {N}$|implies that every permutably convergent series is absolutely convergent. Since there are models of constructive mathematics in which the Riemann permutation theorem for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Constructive notions of equicontinuity.Douglas S. Bridges - 2009 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 48 (5):437-448.
    In the informal setting of Bishop-style constructive reverse mathematics we discuss the connection between the antithesis of Specker’s theorem, Ishihara’s principle BD-N, and various types of equicontinuity. In particular, we prove that the implication from pointwise equicontinuity to uniform sequential equicontinuity is equivalent to the antithesis of Specker’s theorem; and that, for a family of functions on a separable metric space, the implication from uniform sequential equicontinuity to uniform equicontinuity is equivalent to BD-N.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations