Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. (1 other version)Hyperclassical logic (aka independence-friendly logic) and its general significance.Jaakko Hintikka - 2002 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 8 (3):404-423.
    Let us assume that you are entrusted by UNESCO with an important task. You are asked to devise a universal logical language, a Begriffsschrift in Frege's sense, which is to serve the purposes of science, business and everyday life. What requirements should such a “conceptual notation” satisfy? There are undoubtedly many relevant desiderata, but here I am focusing on one unmistakable one. In order to be a viable lingua universalis, your language must in any case be capable of representing any (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Truth and definite truth.Tapani Hyttinen & Gabriel Sandu - 2004 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 126 (1-3):49-55.
    In this paper we consider truth as a vague predicate and inquire into the relation between truth and definite truth. We use some tools from modal logic to clarify this distinction, as done in McGee . Finally, we consider the question whether some of the results given by McGee can be transferred to the case in which the underlying logic is stronger than first-order logic. The result will be seen to be negative.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hierarchies in transitive closure logic, stratified Datalog and infinitary logic.Erich Grädel & Gregory L. McColm - 1996 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 77 (2):169-199.
    We establish a general hierarchy theorem for quantifier classes in the infinitary logic L∞ωωon finite structures. In particular, it is shown that no infinitary formula with bounded number of universal quantifiers can express the negation of a transitive closure.This implies the solution of several open problems in finite model theory: On finite structures, positive transitive closure logic is not closed under negation. More generally the hierarchy defined by interleaving negation and transitive closure operators is strict. This proves a conjecture of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Henkin Quantifiers and Complete Problems.Andreas Blass & Yuri Gurevich - 1986 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 32:1--16.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Ways of branching quantifers.Gila Sher - 1990 - Linguistics and Philosophy 13 (4):393 - 422.
    Branching quantifiers were first introduced by L. Henkin in his 1959 paper ‘Some Remarks on Infmitely Long Formulas’. By ‘branching quantifiers’ Henkin meant a new, non-linearly structured quantiiier-prefix whose discovery was triggered by the problem of interpreting infinitistic formulas of a certain form} The branching (or partially-ordered) quantifier-prefix is, however, not essentially infinitistic, and the issues it raises have largely been discussed in the literature in the context of finitistic logic, as they will be here. Our discussion transcends, however, the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • (1 other version)An Ehrenfeucht-Fraisse class game.Wafik Boulos Lotfallah - 2004 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 50 (2):179-188.
    This paper introduces a new Ehrenfeucht‐Fraïssé type game that is played on two classes of models rather than just two models. This game extends and generalizes the known Ajtai‐Fagin game to the case when there are several alternating (coloring) moves played in different models. The game allows Duplicator to delay her choices of the models till (practically) the very end of the game, making it easier for her to win. This adds on the toolkit of winning strategies for Duplicator in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)An Ehrenfeucht‐Fraïssé class game.Wafik Boulos Lotfallah - 2004 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 50 (2):179-188.
    This paper introduces a new Ehrenfeucht-Fraïssé type game that is played on two classes of models rather than just two models. This game extends and generalizes the known Ajtai-Fagin game to the case when there are several alternating moves played in different models. The game allows Duplicator to delay her choices of the models till the very end of the game, making it easier for her to win. This adds on the toolkit of winning strategies for Duplicator in Ehrenfeucht-Fraïssé type (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A defense of branching quantification.Michael Hand - 1993 - Synthese 95 (3):419 - 432.
    Adding branching quantification to a first-order language increases the expressive power of the language,without adding to its ontology. The present paper is a defense of this claim against Quine (1970) and Patton (1991).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Complete Logics for Elementary Team Properties.Juha Kontinen & Fan Yang - forthcoming - Journal of Symbolic Logic:1-41.
    In this paper, we introduce a logic based on team semantics, called $\mathbf {FOT} $, whose expressive power is elementary, i.e., coincides with first-order logic both on the level of sentences and (possibly open) formulas, and we also show that a sublogic of $\mathbf {FOT} $, called $\mathbf {FOT}^{\downarrow } $, captures exactly downward closed elementary (or first-order) team properties. We axiomatize completely the logic $\mathbf {FOT} $, and also extend the known partial axiomatization of dependence logic to dependence logic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Equilibrium semantics of languages of imperfect information.Merlijn Sevenster & Gabriel Sandu - 2010 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 161 (5):618-631.
    In this paper, we introduce a new approach to independent quantifiers, as originally introduced in Informational independence as a semantic phenomenon by Hintikka and Sandu [9] under the header of independence-friendly languages. Unlike other approaches, which rely heavily on compositional methods, we shall analyze independent quantifiers via equilibriums in strategic games. In this approach, coined equilibrium semantics, the value of an IF sentence on a particular structure is determined by the expected utility of the existential player in any of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Faut-il enterrer le principe de compositionnalitè?François Rivenc - 1995 - Dialogue 34 (2):305-.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Definability hierarchies of general quantifiers.Lauri Hella - 1989 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 43 (3):235.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Classical Negation and Game-Theoretical Semantics.Tero Tulenheimo - 2014 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 55 (4):469-498.
    Typical applications of Hintikka’s game-theoretical semantics give rise to semantic attributes—truth, falsity—expressible in the $\Sigma^{1}_{1}$-fragment of second-order logic. Actually a much more general notion of semantic attribute is motivated by strategic considerations. When identifying such a generalization, the notion of classical negation plays a crucial role. We study two languages, $L_{1}$ and $L_{2}$, in both of which two negation signs are available: $\rightharpoondown $ and $\sim$. The latter is the usual GTS negation which transposes the players’ roles, while the former (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Independence-friendly logic and axiomatic set theory.Jaakko Hintikka - 2004 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 126 (1-3):313-333.
    In order to be able to express all possible patterns of dependence and independence between variables, we have to replace the traditional first-order logic by independence-friendly (IF) logic. Our natural concept of truth for a quantificational sentence S says that all the Skolem functions for S exist. This conception of truth for a sufficiently rich IF first-order language can be expressed in the same language. In a first-order axiomatic set theory, one can apparently express this same concept in set-theoretical terms, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Partially ordered connectives and monadic monotone strict np.Lauri Hella, Merlijn Sevenster & Tero Tulenheimo - 2008 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 17 (3):323-344.
    Motivated by constraint satisfaction problems, Feder and Vardi (SIAM Journal of Computing, 28, 57–104, 1998) set out to search for fragments of satisfying the dichotomy property: every problem definable in is either in P or else NP-complete. Feder and Vardi considered in this connection two logics, strict NP (or SNP) and monadic, monotone, strict NP without inequalities (or MMSNP). The former consists of formulas of the form , where is a quantifier-free formula in a relational vocabulary; and the latter is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Dependence of variables construed as an atomic formula.Jouko Väänänen & Wilfrid Hodges - 2010 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 161 (6):817-828.
    We define a logic capable of expressing dependence of a variable on designated variables only. Thus has similar goals to the Henkin quantifiers of [4] and the independence friendly logic of [6] that it much resembles. The logic achieves these goals by realizing the desired dependence declarations of variables on the level of atomic formulas. By [3] and [17], ability to limit dependence relations between variables leads to existential second order expressive power. Our avoids some difficulties arising in the original (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A Remark on Negation in Dependence Logic.Juha Kontinen & Jouko Väänänen - 2011 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 52 (1):55-65.
    We show that for any pair $\phi$ and $\psi$ of contradictory formulas of dependence logic there is a formula $\theta$ of the same logic such that $\phi\equiv\theta$ and $\psi\equiv\neg\theta$. This generalizes a result of Burgess.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • On the First-Order Prefix Hierarchy.Eric Rosen - 2005 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 46 (2):147-164.
    We investigate the expressive power of fragments of first-order logic that are defined in terms of prefixes. The main result establishes a strict hierarchy among these fragments over the signature consisting of a single binary relation. It implies that for each prefix p, there is a sentence in prenex normal form with prefix p, over a single binary relation, such that for all sentences θ in prenex normal form, if θ is equivalent to , then p can be embedded in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Expressing Second-order Sentences in Intuitionistic Dependence Logic.Fan Yang - 2013 - Studia Logica 101 (2):323-342.
    Intuitionistic dependence logic was introduced by Abramsky and Väänänen [1] as a variant of dependence logic under a general construction of Hodges’ (trump) team semantics. It was proven that there is a translation from intuitionistic dependence logic sentences into second order logic sentences. In this paper, we prove that the other direction is also true, therefore intuitionistic dependence logic is equivalent to second order logic on the level of sentences.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • A Remark on Henkin Sentences and Their Contraries.John P. Burgess - 2003 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 44 (3):185-188.
    That the result of flipping quantifiers and negating what comes after, applied to branching-quantifier sentences, is not equivalent to the negation of the original has been known for as long as such sentences have been studied. It is here pointed out that this syntactic operation fails in the strongest possible sense to correspond to any operation on classes of models.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • On definability in dependence logic.Juha Kontinen & Jouko Väänänen - 2009 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 18 (3):317-332.
    We study the expressive power of open formulas of dependence logic introduced in Väänänen [Dependence logic (Vol. 70 of London Mathematical Society Student Texts), 2007]. In particular, we answer a question raised by Wilfrid Hodges: how to characterize the sets of teams definable by means of identity only in dependence logic, or equivalently in independence friendly logic.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Hintikka and the Functions of Logic.Montgomery Link - 2019 - Logica Universalis 13 (2):203-217.
    Jaakko Hintikka points out the power of Skolem functions to affect both what there is and what we know. There is a tension in his presupposition that these functions actually extend the realm of logic. He claims to have resolved the tension by “reconstructing constructivism” along epistemological lines, instead of by a typical ontological construction; however, after the collapse of the distinction between first and second order, that resolution is not entirely satisfactory. Still, it does throw light on the conceptual (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Hintikka’s Independence-Friendly Logic Meets Nelson’s Realizability.Sergei P. Odintsov, Stanislav O. Speranski & Igor Yu Shevchenko - 2018 - Studia Logica 106 (3):637-670.
    Inspired by Hintikka’s ideas on constructivism, we are going to ‘effectivize’ the game-theoretic semantics for independence-friendly first-order logic, but in a somewhat different way than he did in the monograph ‘The Principles of Mathematics Revisited’. First we show that Nelson’s realizability interpretation—which extends the famous Kleene’s realizability interpretation by adding ‘strong negation’—restricted to the implication-free first-order formulas can be viewed as an effective version of GTS for FOL. Then we propose a realizability interpretation for IF-FOL, inspired by the so-called ‘trump (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On The Computational Consequences of Independence in Propositional Logic.Merlijn Sevenster - 2006 - Synthese 149 (2):257-283.
    Sandu and Pietarinen [Partiality and Games: Propositional Logic. Logic J. IGPL 9 (2001) 101] study independence friendly propositional logics. That is, traditional propositional logic extended by means of syntax that allow connectives to be independent of each other, although the one may be subordinate to the other. Sandu and Pietarinen observe that the IF propositional logics have exotic properties, like functional completeness for three-valued functions. In this paper we focus on one of their IF propositional logics and study its properties, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Decidability problems in languages with Henkin quantifiers.Michał Krynicki & Marcin Mostowski - 1992 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 58 (2):149-172.
    Krynicki, M. and M. Mostowski, Decidability problems in languages with Henkin quantifiers, Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 58 149–172.We consider the language L with all Henkin quantifiers Hn defined as follows: Hnx1…xny1…yn φ iff f1…fnx1. ..xn φ, ...,fn). We show that the theory of equality in L is undecidable. The proof of this result goes by interpretation of the word problem for semigroups.Henkin quantifiers are strictly related to the function quantifiers Fn defined as follows: Fnx1…xny1…yn φ iff fx1…xn φ,...,f). (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Partially-ordered (branching) generalized quantifiers: A general definition.Gila Sher - 1997 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 26 (1):1-43.
    Following Henkin's discovery of partially-ordered (branching) quantification (POQ) with standard quantifiers in 1959, philosophers of language have attempted to extend his definition to POQ with generalized quantifiers. In this paper I propose a general definition of POQ with 1-place generalized quantifiers of the simplest kind: namely, predicative, or "cardinality" quantifiers, e.g., "most", "few", "finitely many", "exactly α", where α is any cardinal, etc. The definition is obtained in a series of generalizations, extending the original, Henkin definition first to a general (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Independendly‐Friendly Logic: Dependence and Independence of Quantifiers in Logic.Gabriel Sandu - 2012 - Philosophy Compass 7 (10):691-711.
    Independence‐Friendly logic introduced by Hintikka and Sandu studies patterns of dependence and independence of quantifiers which exceed those found in ordinary first‐order logic. The present survey focuses on the game‐theoretical interpretation of IF‐logic, including connections to solution concepts in classical game theory, but we shall also present its compositional interpretation together with its connections to notions of dependence and dependence between terms.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Henkin and function quantifiers.Michael Krynicki & Jouko Väänänen - 1989 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 43 (3):273-292.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Quantifiers in natural languages: Some logical problems II. [REVIEW]Jaakko Hintikka - 1977 - Linguistics and Philosophy 1 (2):153 - 172.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • On elementary logics for quantitative dependencies.Miika Hannula, Minna Hirvonen & Juha Kontinen - 2022 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 173 (10):103104.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Lottery Semantics: A Compositional Semantics for Probabilistic First-Order Logic with Imperfect Information.Pietro Galliani & Allen L. Mann - 2013 - Studia Logica 101 (2):293-322.
    We present a compositional semantics for first-order logic with imperfect information that is equivalent to Sevenster and Sandu’s equilibrium semantics (under which the truth value of a sentence in a finite model is equal to the minimax value of its semantic game). Our semantics is a generalization of an earlier semantics developed by the first author that was based on behavioral strategies, rather than mixed strategies.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • An undecidable extension of Morley's theorem on the number of countable models.Christopher J. Eagle, Clovis Hamel, Sandra Müller & Franklin D. Tall - 2023 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 174 (9):103317.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Alternating (In)Dependence-Friendly Logic.Dylan Bellier, Massimo Benerecetti, Dario Della Monica & Fabio Mogavero - 2023 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 174 (10):103315.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark