Switch to: References

Citations of:

S

In Allgemeiner Kantindex Zu Kants Gesammelten Schriften. Band. 20. Abt. 3: Personenindex Zu Kants Gesammelten Schriften. De Gruyter. pp. 112-126 (1969)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Kant's Pragmatism.Tobias Henschen - 2013 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 21 (1):165-176.
    This article offers a definition of the term "pragmatic", as it is used in Kant's Critique of Pure Reason. The definition offered does not make any reference to the affinities between Kant's pragmatism and the philosophies of the American or other pragmatists but draws its definiens entirely from the Kantian conceptual framework. It states that the term "pragmatic" denotes imperatives, laws and beliefs of a specific type: an imperative is pragmatic if and only if it is concerned with the choice (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Kant on real definitions in geometry.Jeremy Heis - 2014 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 44 (5-6):605-630.
    This paper gives a contextualized reading of Kant's theory of real definitions in geometry. Though Leibniz, Wolff, Lambert and Kant all believe that definitions in geometry must be ‘real’, they disagree about what a real definition is. These disagreements are made vivid by looking at two of Euclid's definitions. I argue that Kant accepted Euclid's definition of circle and rejected his definition of parallel lines because his conception of mathematics placed uniquely stringent requirements on real definitions in geometry. Leibniz, Wolff (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Husserl’s Crisis and Our Crisis.Robert Hanna - 2014 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 22 (5):752-770.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Between πόλεμος and δύναμις: the notion of power as origin of the noble and slave morality in Nietzsche’s On the genealogy of morals.Hernan Esteban Guerrero-Troncoso - 2019 - Filosofia Unisinos 20 (2).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Negativ opdragelse og negation af opdragelse. Émiles aktualitet i forhold til en kritisk teori om pædagogik.Andreas Gruschka - 2013 - Studier i Pædagogisk Filosofi 2 (1):21-33.
    Rousseau's exposition of negative education in Émile is explored through its relation to the concept of a negative theory of education developed by the author as a continuation of some crucial insights of early critical theory. Thus, the essay elaborates different aspects of negation and negativity in relation to educational theory and practice. The author defends thereby the actuality of Rousseau's philosophy of education for a critical understanding of the modern phenomenon of educationalization.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • ‘I Knew Jean-Paul Sartre’: Philosophy of education as comedy.Morwenna Griffiths & Michael A. Peters - 2014 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 46 (2):1-16.
    Ludwig Wittgenstein suggests that ?A serious and good philosophical work could be written consisting entirely of jokes?. The idea for this dialogue comes from a conversation that Michael Peters and Morwenna Griffiths had at the Philosophy of Education of Great Britain annual meeting at the University of Oxford, 2011. It was sparked by an account of an assessment of a piece of work where one of the external examiners unexpectedly exclaimed ?I knew Jean-Paul Sartre?, trying to trump the discussion. This (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Rescued Legacy and a Jazz Model: Mapping Kant’s “Critique of Aesthetic Judgment”’s Twentieth- Century Reception.Silvestre Gristina - 2020 - Con-Textos Kantianos 1 (12):603-613.
    Review of: Marino, Stefano, Terzi, Pietro, Kant’s “Critique of Aesthetic Judgment” in the 20 th Century. A Companion to Its Main Interpretations, Berlin/Boston, Walter De Gruyter, 2020, pp. 361, ISBN 978-3-11-059613-7.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Das ontologische dilemma der normativen ethik.Dirk Greimann - 2003 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 34 (1):15-41.
    The Ontological Dilemma of Normative Ethics. This paper pursues two goals. The first is to show that normative ethics is confronted with the following dilemma: to be coherent, this discipline is ontologically committed to acknowledge the existence of objective values, but, to be scientifically respectable, it is committed to repudiate such values. The second goal is to assess the possible solutions to this dilemma. To this end, the following strategies are discussed: Kant’s constructive objectivism, Jürgen Habermas’ “epistemic ersatzism”, Franz von (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • November 1751 − April 1752.Johann Christoph Gottsched - 2023 - De Gruyter.
    Ein Hauptthema des 18. Bandes mit Briefen von November 1751 bis April 1752 ist die Sorge um den prominenten katholischen Theologen Franz Ignaz Rothfischer, der im November 1751 in Leipzig zur lutherischen Konfession konvertierte. In enger Abstimmung mit dem Reichsgrafen Friedrich Heinrich von Seckendorff bemühte sich Gottsched um dessen beruflichen Neustart, Rothfischer wurde Professor in Helmstedt. Gottscheds vertraute Korrespondenten Flottwell, Scheyb und Brucker berichten aus Königsberg, Wien und Augsburg wie gewohnt über ihre Projekte und Ereignisse aus ihrem Umfeld. Christoph Otto (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Unity and objectivity in Strawson and Cassam.Anil Gomes - 2021 - Analytic Philosophy 62 (1):84-96.
    Some comments on Quassim Cassam’s Self and World written for a conference at the Institute of Philosophy in 2017. I consider the objection that Cassam raises to Strawson’s argument from unity to objectivity in The Bounds of Sense and raise some general questions about Cassam’s problem of misconception and its application to transcendental arguments.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Sensation and the Stimulus: Psychophysics and the Prehistory of the Marburg School.Marco Giovanelli - 2017 - Perspectives on Science 25 (3):287-323.
    In 1912, Ernst Cassirer contributed to the special issue of the Kant-Studien that honored Hermann Cohen's retirement—his mentor and teacher, and the recognized founding father of the so-called 'Marburg school' of Neo-Kantianism. In the context of an otherwise rather conventional presentation of Cohen's interpretation of Kant, Cassirer made a remark that is initially surprising. It is “anything but accurate,” he wrote, to regard Cohen's philosophy as focused “exclusively on the mathematical theory of nature,” as is usually done. A reconstruction of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • In Defence of the One-Act View: Reply to Guyer.Hannah Ginsborg - 2017 - British Journal of Aesthetics 57 (4):421-435.
    I defend my ‘one-act’ interpretation of Kant’s account of judgments of beauty against recent criticisms by Paul Guyer. Guyer’s text-based arguments for his own ‘two-acts’ view rely on the assumption that a claim to the universal validity of one’s pleasure presupposes the prior existence of the pleasure. I argue that pleasure in the beautiful claims its own universal validity, thus obviating the need to distinguish two independent acts of judging. The resulting view, I argue, is closer to the text and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Criminal Responsibility and the Living Self.Thomas Giddens - 2015 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 9 (2):189-206.
    Behaviour, including criminal behaviour, takes place in lived contexts of embodied action and experience. The way in which abstract models of selfhood efface the individual as a unique, living being is a central aspect of the ‘ethical-other’ debate; if an individual is modelled as abstracted from this ‘living’ context, that individual cannot be properly or meaningfully linked with his or her behaviour, and thus cannot justly be understood as responsible. The dominant rational choice models of criminal identity in legal theory (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Das Lächeln der Roboter: Was uns morgen in der Kunst bewegt.Martin Gessmann - 2020 - Internationales Jahrbuch Für Medienphilosophie 6 (1):277-296.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ginsborg, Hannah. The Normativity of Nature. Oxford University Press, 2015, 364 pp., $40.00 paper. [REVIEW]Gerad Gentry - 2016 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 74 (1):115-117.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Nature of the Critique of Pure Reason and the Architectonic Unity of Metaphysics: A Response to my Critics.Gabriele Gava - 2024 - Kantian Review 29 (1).
    I respond to Karin de Boer, Thomas Land, and Claudio La Rocca’s comments on Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason and the Method of Metaphysics (CUP 2023). I first provide a quick outline of some of the main claims I make in the book. I then directly address their criticisms, which I group into three categories. The first group of comments raises doubts concerning my characterization of the central tasks of the critique of pure reason. The second targets the fact that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Pure and Impure Philosophy in Kant's Metaphilosophy.Ernesto V. Garcia - 2023 - Kantian Journal 42 (3):17-48.
    Kant’s metaphilosophy has three main parts: (1) an essentialist project (“What is philosophy?”); (2) a methodological project (“How do we do philosophy?”); and (3) a taxonomic project (“What are the different parts of philosophy, and how are they related?”). This paper focuses on the third project. In particular, it explores one of the most intriguing yet puzzling aspects of Kant’s philosophy, viz. the relationship between what Kant calls ‘pure’ philosophy vs. ‘applied’, ‘empirical’ or what we can broadly refer to as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kant's ‘Doctrine of Right’: A Commentary.D. Gamble - 2014 - Philosophical Quarterly 64 (255):340-343.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Nihilism and Metaphysics: The Third Voyage.Daniel B. Gallagher (ed.) - 2014 - Albany: State University of New York Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Marx with Kant on exploitation.James Furner - 2015 - Contemporary Political Theory 14 (1):23-44.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Meaning and Aesthetic Judgment in Kant.Eli Friedlander - 2006 - Philosophical Topics 34 (1-2):21-34.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • German Idealism and Tragic Maturity.Shterna Friedman - 2020 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 32 (4):458-492.
    Isaiah Berlin viewed value conflict as tragic, as it requires the sacrifice of some values for others. It is a mark of maturity, he thought, to accept this tragic truth. This view raises certain conceptual problems that can be attributed to Berlin’s subtle departures from the German authors (Kant, Schelling, and Hegel) who originated the doctrine of tragic maturity—figures who had, in turn, transformed the earlier idea that enlightenment is a natural and morally neutral process of maturation. Kant moralized the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kierkegaard's Use of German Philosophy.Roe Fremstedal - 2015 - In Jon Stewart (ed.), A Companion to Kierkegaard. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 36–49.
    This chapter deals with German philosophy from Leibniz to Fichte, which formed an important part of Kierkegaard's intellectual background. In this period German philosophy came to dominate Danish philosophy. However, Kierkegaard's attitude toward his German predecessors is generally ambivalent, involving both critique and admiration. Although Kierkegaard was fluent in German and very familiar with classic German philosophy, his use of this philosophy is somewhat eclectic and assimilated to his own ends. Kierkegaard uses his German predecessors to develop a distinction between (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Soul Dust: The Magic of Consciousness.K. Frankish - 2014 - Philosophical Quarterly 64 (255):338-340.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Jüdische Namen in deutschsprachiger Dichtung.Margit Frank - 1992 - Nordisk judaistik/Scandinavian Jewish Studies 13 (1):12-22.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kant’s Moderate Cynicism and the Harmony between Virtue and Worldly Happiness.David Forman - 2016 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 54 (1):75-109.
    For Kant, any authentic moral demands are wholly distinct from the demands of prudence. This has led critics to complain that Kantian moral demands are incompatible with our human nature as happiness-seekers. Kant’s defenders have pointed out, correctly, that Kant can and does assert that it is permissible, at least in principle, to pursue our own happiness. But this response does not eliminate the worry that a life organized around the pursuit of virtue might turn out to be one from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Once More unto the Breach: Kant and Race.Samuel Fleischacker - 2023 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 61 (1):3-28.
    The last thirty years has seen an explosion of literature on Kant and race. Once overlooked essays and notes in which Kant expresses contempt for nonwhite people and support for slavery have been brought to light, and many scholars have wrestled with the question of how a philosopher who stressed the equal dignity of all human beings could hold such views. This article tries to reframe the debate over these issues. It begins by reviewing the racist texts in Kant's corpus (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Philosopher's Voice: Philosophy, Politics, and Language in the Nineteenth Century.Andrew Fiala - 2002 - Albany: State University of New York Press.
    _Explores the relationship between philosophy and politics in the work of Kant, Fichte, Hegel, and Marx._.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Politics, History and Logic in Max Weber.Maurizio Ferrera - 2024 - History and Philosophy of Logic 45 (1):4-19.
    The article illustrates the different meanings of the term “logic” in Weber's work and then proceeds to discuss his approach to the explanation of historical events and in particular to counterfactual analysis. Weber's epistemology is first situated within the neo-Kantian debates of his time as well as legal positivism and historical jurisprudence. The article then focuses on this author's conception of science as a value sphere, on the aims and methods of explanation in the social and historical sciences and on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Colloquium 3: Aristotle On ΦANTAΣIA.Alfredo Ferrarin - 2006 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 21 (1):89-123.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Praxis and Agency in Foucault’s Historiography.Lynn Fendler - 2004 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 23 (5):445-466.
    This paper examines the consequences for agency that Foucault’s historiographical approach constructs. The analysis begins by explaining the difference between ‘legislative history’ and ‘exemplary history,’ drawing parallels to similar theoretical distinctions offered in the works of Max Weber, J.L. Austin, and Zygmunt Bauman. The analysis continues by reading Habermas’s critique of Foucault through the tropological lenses suggested by White [Metahistory. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1973]; it argues that Habermas’s critique misrecognizes the tropes of Foucaultian genealogy. The paper draws (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kant's Table of Judgments and the Doctrine of the Judgment in the German Logic of XVIIIth Century.Yurij Fedorchenko - 2015 - Sententiae 32 (1):47-59.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kant's Way to the Table of Categories.Yurij Fedorchenko - 2014 - Sententiae 31 (2):121-133.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Humanity as a Duty to Oneself.Sunday Adeniyi Fasoro - 2019 - Con-Textos Kantianos 9:220-237.
    This paper analyses the thorny interpretative puzzle surrounding the connection between humanity and the good will. It discusses this puzzle: if the good will is the only good without qualification, why does Kant claim that humanity is something possessing an absolute value? It explores the answers to this question within Kantian scholarship; answers that emanate from a commitment to the human capacity for freedom and morality and to actual obedience to the moral law. In its final analysis, it endorses Richard (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Philosophy and the "man" in the humanities.Emmanuel Chukwudi Eze - 1999 - Topoi 18 (1):49-58.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Reason and Experience in Mendelssohn and Kant: by Paul Guyer, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2020, viii + 361 pp., €41.85 ($50.00) (hbk), ISBN: 9780198850335. [REVIEW]Ekin Erkan - 2021 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 29 (2):268-274.
    Although scholars such as Norbert Hinske and Daniel Dahlstrom have produced chapters and articles dealing with various points of confluence between Moses Mendelssohn and Kant, Paul Guyer’s Reason a...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Phenomenological Kant: Heidegger's Interest in Transcendental Philosophy.Chad Engelland - 2010 - Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 41 (2):150-169.
    This paper provides a new, comprehensive overview of Martin Heidegger’s interpretations of Immanuel Kant. Its aim is to identify Heidegger’s motive in interpreting Kant and to distinguish, for the first time, the four phases of Heidegger’s reading of Kant. The promise of the “phenomenological Kant” gave Heidegger entrance to a rich domain of investigation. In four phases and with reference to Husserl, Heidegger interpreted Kant as first falling short of phenomenology (1919-1925), then approaching phenomenology (1925-1927), then advancing phenomenology (1927-1929), and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Conceptual Origin of Worldview in Kant and Fichte.Alexander T. Englert - 2023 - Journal of Transcendental Philosophy 4 (1):1-24.
    Kant and Fichte developed the concept of a worldview as a way of reflecting on experience as a whole. But what does it mean to form a worldview? And what role did it play in the German Idealist tradition? This paper seeks to answer these questions through a detailed analysis of the form of a philosophical worldview and its historical portent, both of which remain unexplored in the literature. The dearth of attention is partially to blame on Kant’s desultory development (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Vienna Circle and the Uppsala School as philosophical inspirations for the Scandinavian Legal Realism.Katarzyna Eliasz & Marek Jakubiec - 2016 - Semina Scientiarum 15:107-123.
    The Uppsala School in philosophy and the Vienna Circle are prima facie similar currents in contemporary philosophy. Both reject metaphysics, claim that reality is a spatio­‑temporal realm and adhere to noncognitivism in terms of values. However, justifications of these assumptions are quite different. In the following article we reconstruct main theses of both mentioned currents and then we indicate their impact on one of the major jurisprudential movements, namely Scandinavian Legal Realism. We focus on Alf Ross’ legal philosophy, as it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Freedom in Responsibility: On the Relevance of “Sin” As a Hermeneutic Guiding Principle in Bioethical Decision Making.Elisabeth Gräb-Schmidt - 2005 - Christian Bioethics 11 (2):147-165.
    (2005). Freedom in Responsibility: On the Relevance of “Sin” As a Hermeneutic Guiding Principle in Bioethical Decision Making. Christian Bioethics: Vol. 11, No. 2, pp. 147-165.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • The divorce of reason and experience: Kant's paralogisms of pure reason in context.Corey W. Dyck - 2009 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 47 (2):pp. 249-275.
    I consider Kant's criticism of rational psychology in the Paralogisms of Pure Reason in light of his German predecessors. I first present Wolff's foundational account of metaphysical psychology with the result that Wolff's rational psychology is not comfortably characterized as a naïvely rationalist psychology. I then turn to the reception of Wolff's account among later German metaphysicians, and show that the same claim of a dependence of rational upon empirical psychology is found in the publications and lectures of Kant's pre-Critical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The legend of the justified true belief analysis.Julien Dutant - 2015 - Philosophical Perspectives 29 (1):95-145.
    There is a traditional conception of knowledge but it is not the Justified True Belief analysis Gettier attacked. On the traditional view, knowledge consists in having a belief that bears a discernible mark of truth. A mark of truth is a truth-entailing property: a property that only true beliefs can have. It is discernible if one can always tell that a belief has it, that is, a sufficiently attentive subject believes that a belief has it if and only if it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Laws of nature in Kant’s critical philosophy: Michela Massimi and Angela Breitenbach, Eds.: Kant and the laws of nature. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2017, $99.99 HB.Katherine Dunlop - 2018 - Metascience 28 (1):133-138.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Karl Popper a sepětí vědecké metody a demokracie.Pavel Doleček - 2012 - Teorie Vědy / Theory of Science 34 (4):439-467.
    Článek se zabývá způsobem, jakým vnímá vztah vědecké metody a demokracie Karl Popper. Toto sepětí je jedním ze základních atributů Popperova myšlení. Pro jeho pochopení je třeba zasadit Poppera do historického kontextu vývoje liberálního myšlení a poukázat na možné souvislosti se Schumpeterovou redefinicí demokracie. Výchozím bodem je však interpretace základních episte- mologických předpokladů Popperova myšlení - konceptů provizornosti vědeckého poznání a ratio negativa. Primárním cílem článku je kontextualizace těchto předpokladů s politologickými a sociologickými důsledky. Ty lze spatřovat nejen s odmítnutím (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Deconstructive constitutionalism: Derrida reading Kant.Jacques De Ville - 2023 - Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.
    Investigates, by way of Derrida's engagements with Kant, how the foundations of modern constitutionalism can be differently conceived to address some of the challenges of the twenty-first century.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Defining a context for Otto Friedrich gruppe's 'revolution' in nineteenth-century philosophy.Herbert De Vriese & Guido Vanheeswijck - 2006 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 14 (3):489 – 511.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Nietzsche’s Practices of Illusion.Astrid Deuber-Mankowsky - 2017 - Critical Horizons 18 (4):307-332.
    This essay examines the complex topic of illusion and art in Nietzsche’s philosophy. It focuses on two topics in particular: Nietzsche’s practice of self-transformation; and the question of how to differentiate through the analysis of style those practices that are deluded from those that are transformative.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Leibniz in the Eighteenth Century: Herder's Critical Reflections on the Principles of Nature and Grace.Nigel DeSouza - 2012 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 20 (4):773-795.
    The subject of this article is Herder’s unique conception of the soul-body relationship and its divergence from and dependence on Leibniz. Herder’s theory is premised on a rejection of the windowlessness of monads in two important respects: interaction between material bodies (as gleaned from Crusius and Kant) and interaction between the soul and body. Herder’s theory depends on Leibniz insofar as it agrees with the intimate connection Leibniz posits between the soul and the body, as his epistemology demonstrates, with, however, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Art, Origins, Otherness: Between Philosophy and Art.William Desmond - 2003 - State University of New York Press.
    Addresses the end of art and the task of metaphysics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • On the possibility of speculative ethical absolutes after Kant: Returning to Schelling through the frailties of meillassoux and Badiou.Drew M. Dalton - 2016 - Angelaki 21 (4):157-172.
    According to Quentin Meillassoux, one of the principal aims of speculative philosophy “must be the immanent inscription of values in being.” In this regard, the return to speculation in contemporary philosophy is in many ways a deeply ethical project. This “inscription of values” can only be successful, however, if it can somehow assert an absolute ethical value without, on the one hand, resorting to the kind of dogmatism laid to rest by the Kantian critique; or, on the other, by falling (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark