Switch to: References

Citations of:

Posidonius on emotions

In A. A. Long (ed.), Problems in Stoicism. London,: Athlone Press (1971)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Modernity and Plato: two paradigms of rationality.Arbogast Schmitt - 2012 - Rochester, N.Y.: Camden House.
    Sets itself the Herculean task of comparing and reconciling the modern and Platonic concepts of rationality.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Stoicism bibliography.Ronald H. Epp - 1985 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 23 (S1):125-171.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Feeling without thinking: Lessons from the ancients on emotion and virtue-acquisition.Amy Coplan - 2010 - Metaphilosophy 41 (1-2):132-151.
    By briefly sketching some important ancient accounts of the connections between psychology and moral education, I hope to illuminate the significance of the contemporary debate on the nature of emotion and to reveal its stakes. I begin the essay with a brief discussion of intellectualism in Socrates and the Stoics, and Plato's and Posidonius's respective attacks against it. Next, I examine the two current leading philosophical accounts of emotion: the cognitive theory and the noncognitive theory. I maintain that the noncognitive (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Posidonius on Virtue and the Good.Severin Gotz - 2023 - Classical Quarterly 73 (2):636-647.
    This paper argues that despite recent tendencies to minimize the differences between Posidonius and the Early Stoics, there are some important aspects of Stoic ethics in which Posidonius deviated from the orthodox doctrine. According to two passages in Diogenes Laertius, Posidonius counted health and wealth among the goods and held that virtue alone is insufficient for happiness. While Kidd in his commentary dismissed this report as spurious, there are good reasons to take Diogenes’ remarks seriously. Through a careful analysis of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Posidonius on Emotions and Non-Conceptual Content.Bill Wringe - 2011 - Prolegomena 10 (2):185-213.
    In this paper I argue that the work of the unorthodox Stoic Posidonius - as reported to us by Galen - can be seen as making an interesting contribution to contemporary debates about the nature of emotion. Richard Sorabji has already argued that Posidonius' contribution highlights the weaknesses in some well-known contemporary forms of cognitivism. Here I argue that Posidonius might be seen as advocating a theory of the emotions which sees them as being, in at least some cases, two-level (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Colloquium 4.David Sedley - 1991 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 7 (1):146-157.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Human Autonomy and its Limits in the Thought of Origen of Alexandria.Kathleen Gibbons - 2016 - Classical Quarterly 66 (2):673-690.
    As the church historian Henri Crouzel observed, questions about the nature of human autonomy were central to the thought of the third-century theologian Origen of Alexandria. On this question, his influence on later generations, though complicated, would be difficult to overstate. Yet, what exactly Origen thought autonomy required has been a subject of debate. On one widespread reading, he has been taken to argue that autonomy requires that human beings have the capacity to act otherwise than they do in fact (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Commentary on Gill.Christopher A. Dustin - 1996 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 12 (1):226-246.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Scipio Aemilianus and Greek Ethics.Jonathan Barlow - 2018 - Classical Quarterly 68 (1):112-127.
    Philosophical influences in the personality and public life of Publius Cornelius Scipio Aemilianus, consul in 147 and 134b.c., were once emphasized in scholarship. In 1892, Schmekel demonstrated the reception of Stoic philosophy in the second half of the second centuryb.c.among the philhellenic members of the governing elite in general, and statesmen like Scipio Aemilianus in particular, in what he called the ‘Roman Enlightenment’. In the 1920s and 1930s, Kaerst showed influences of Stoic philosophy on Scipio, contemporary politics and the Principate (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark