Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Reasoning to hypotheses: Where do questions come?Matti Sintonen - 2004 - Foundations of Science 9 (3):249-266.
    Detectives and scientists are in the business of reasoning from observations to explanations. This they often do by raising cunning questionsduring their inquiries. But to substantiate this claim we need to know how questions arise and how they are nurtured into more specific hypotheses. I shall discuss what the problem is, and then introduce the so-called interrogative model of inquiry which makes use of an explicit logic of questions. On this view, a discovery processes can be represented as a model-based (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Serendipity and vision: Two methods for discovery comments on Nickles.Scott A. Kleiner - 1999 - Biology and Philosophy 14 (1):55-63.
    Thomas Nickles challenges my thesis that innovative discoveries can be based on deliberately chosen problems and research strategies. He suggests that all significant innovation can be seen as such only in retrospect and that its generation must be serendipitous. Here I argue in response that significant innovations can and do often arise from self conscious critical appraisal of orthodox practice combined with regulated though speculative abductive argumentation to alternative explanatory schemata. Orthodox practice is not based upon monolithic systems of belief (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hypothetical and Inductive Heuristics.Scott E. Kleiner - 1990 - Philosophica 45.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Erotetic logic and scientific inquiry.Scott A. Kleiner - 1988 - Synthese 74 (1):19 - 46.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Explanatory coherence and empirical adequacy: The problem of abduction, and the justification of evolutionary models. [REVIEW]Scott A. Kleiner - 2003 - Biology and Philosophy 18 (4):513-527.
    Foundationalist theories of justification for science were undermined by the theory-ladeness thesis, which has affinities with coherentist epistemologies. A challenge for defenders of coherentist theories of scientific justification is to specify coherence relations relevant to science and to show how these relations make the truth of their bearers likely. Coherence relations include characteristics that pick out better explanations in the implementation of abductive arguments. Empiricist philosophers have attacked abductive reasoning by claiming that explanatory virtues are pragmatic, having no implications regarding (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Wallace's travels and theories in the Malay Archipelago.Martin Fichman - 2014 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 47:201-205.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wallace, Darwin, and the Practice of Natural History.Melinda B. Fagan - 2007 - Journal of the History of Biology 40 (4):601 - 635.
    There is a pervasive contrast in the early natural history writings of the co-discoverers of natural selection, Alfred Russel Wallace and Charles Darwin. In his writings from South America and the Malay Archipelago (1848-1852, 1854-1862). Wallace consistently emphasized species and genera, and separated these descriptions from his rarer and briefer discussions of individual organisms. In contrast, Darwin's writings during the Beagle voyage (1831-1836) emphasized individual organisms, and mingled descriptions of individuals and groups. The contrast is explained by the different practices (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Occam’s Razor in science: a case study from biogeography.A. Baker - 2007 - Biology and Philosophy 22 (2):193-215.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations