Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Heidegger and the Supposition of a Single, Objective World.Denis McManus - 2012 - European Journal of Philosophy 23 (2):195-220.
    Christina Lafont has argued that the early Heidegger's reflections on truth and understanding are incompatible with ‘the supposition of a single objective world’. This paper presents her argument, reviews some responses that the existing Heidegger literature suggests, and offers what I argue is a superior response. Building on a deeper exploration of just what the above ‘supposition’ demands, I argue that a crucial assumption that Lafont and Haugeland both accept must be rejected, namely, that different ‘understandings of Being’ can be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Internalism, externalism, and transcendental idealism.Dan Zahavi - 2008 - Synthese 160 (3):355-374.
    The analyses of the mind–world relation offered by transcendental idealists such as Husserl have often been dismissed with the argument that they remain committed to an outdated form of internalism. The first move in this paper will be to argue that there is a tight link between Husserl’s transcendental idealism and what has been called phenomenological externalism, and that Husserl’s endorsement of the former commits him to a version of the latter. Secondly, it will be shown that key elements in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Phenomenological immanence, normativity, and semantic externalism.Steven Crowell - 2008 - Synthese 160 (3):335 - 354.
    This paper argues that transcendental phenomenology (here represented by Edmund Husserl) can accommodate the main thesis of semantic externalism, namely, that intentional content is not simply a matter of what is ‘in the head,’ but depends on how the world is. I first introduce the semantic problem as an issue of how linguistic tokens or mental states can have ‘content’—that is, how they can set up conditions of satisfaction or be responsive to norms such that they can succeed or fail (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Levinas's Philosophy of Perception.Matt E. M. Bower - 2017 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 55 (4):383-414.
    Levinas is usually discussed as a philosopher wrestling with the nature of our experience of others, ethical obligation, and the divine. Unlike other phenomenologists, such as Husserl and Heidegger, he is not often mentioned in discussions about issues in philosophy of mind. His work in that area, especially on perception, is underappreciated. He gives an account of the nature of perceptual experience that is remarkable both in how it departs from that of others in the phenomenological tradition and for how (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On Why Semantic Externalism, Creationist Theism, Personalism, and Veber’s Philosophy Fit Together Very Well.Bojan Žalec - 2016 - Synthesis Philosophica 31 (1):65-82.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reduction, Externalism and Immanence in Husserl and Heidegger.Felix O’Murchadha - 2008 - Synthese 160 (3):375-395.
    This paper argues that the Husserl—Heidegger relationship is systematically misunderstood when framed in terms of a distinction between internalism and externalism. Both philosophers, it is argued, employ the phenomenological reduction to immanence as a fundamental methodological instrument. After first outlining the assumptions regarding inner and outer and the individual and the social from which recent epistemological interpretations of phenomenology begin, I turn to the question of Husserl's internalism. I argue that Husserl can only be understood as an internalist on the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (1 other version)Heidegger, lector de la retórica aristotélica.Jesús Adrián Escudero - 2011 - Dianoia 56 (66):3-29.
    El presente trabajo analiza la productiva asimilación heideggeriana de la retórica aristotélica que encontramos en sus lecciones de 1924, Conceptos fundamentales de la filosofía aristotélica, y su posterior repercusión en los análisis del uno cotidiano y de la habladuría en Ser y tiempo. Primero se presentan las líneas básicas de la interpretación heideggeriana temprana de los escritos prácticos y políticos de Aristóteles (1). Luego se perfila con más detalle su relectura en clave ontológica de la Retórica de Aristóteles, prestando una (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Moral Responsibility for Distant Collective Harms.David Zoller - 2015 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 18 (5):995-1010.
    While it is well recognized that many everyday consumer behaviors, such as purchases of sweatshop goods, come at a cost to the global poor, it has proven difficult to argue that even knowing, repeat contributors are somehow morally complicit in those outcomes. Some recent approaches contend that marginal contributions to distant harms are consequences that consumers straightforwardly should have born in mind, which would make consumers seem reckless or negligent. Critics reasonably reply that the bad luck that my innocent purchase (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Heidegger, Lafont and the necessity of the transcendental.R. Matthew Shockey - 2008 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 34 (5):557-574.
    Cristina Lafont's recent reading of Heidegger offers a powerful formulation of the widespread view that once one recognizes our `facticity' and the role of language in shaping it, there is no room left to talk about transcendental structures of meaning or experience. In this article I challenge this view. I argue that Lafont inaccurately conflates what Heidegger calls our `understanding of being' with that which language discloses. In order to show that the philosophical motivation for this conflation is unsound, I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)Heidegger, leitor da retórica aristotélica.Jesús Adrián Escudero - 2017 - Aufklärung 4 (S2):87-104.
    O presente trabalho analisa a assimilação produtiva heideggeriana da retórica aristotélica que encontramos em suas lições de 1924, Conceitos fundamentais da filosofia aristotélica, e sua posterior repercussão nas análises do impessoal cotidiano e do falatório em Ser e tempo. Primeiro se apresentam as linhas básicas da interpretação do jovem Heidegger dos escritos práticos e políticos de Aristóteles. Em seguida se perfila com mais detalhe sua releitura com explicação ontológica da Retórica de Aristóteles, com especial atenção para o plano da comunicabilidade (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Puzzle of Empty Formal Indications: On the ‘Deferred’ Meaning of Heidegger's Language.David Zoller - forthcoming - European Journal of Philosophy.
    Heidegger's notion of philosophical concepts as “formal indications” is rightly viewed as a crucial development. The idea of formal indication is partly intended to answer concerns that phenomenology objectivizes conscious life. Formal indication responds—in what would become a signature feature of much of Heidegger's early work—by setting up a unique dependency of the meaning of phenomenological concepts on their “enactment” in the first‐personal life of the investigator or reader. Commentators have appropriately wondered whether this move succeeds. Yet relatively little emphasis (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Self and Nature in Heidegger.Paolo Diego Bubbio - 2018 - Research in Phenomenology 48 (2):175-196.
    _ Source: _Volume 48, Issue 2, pp 175 - 196 This article provides an analysis of the development of the notions of “self” and “nature” through three stages of Heidegger’s thought. The main contention is that Heidegger’s conceptions of the self and nature are indissolubly connected to each other, and that such connection appears through three concerns that represent important elements of continuity: 1) the “irreducibility of the self,” conceived in a non-subjectivist way; 2) the recovery of a non-objectivist “originary” (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation