Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Boole's annotations on 'the mathematical analysis of logic'.G. C. Smith - 1983 - History and Philosophy of Logic 4 (1-2):27-39.
    George Boole collected ideas for the improvement of his Mathematical analysis of logic(1847) on interleaved copies of that work. Some of the notes on the interleaves are merely minor changes in explanation. Others amount to considerable extension of method in his mathematical approach to logic. In particular, he developed his technique in solving simultaneous elective equations and handling hypotheticals and elective functions. These notes and extensions provided a source for his later book Laws of thought(1854).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Thomas solly (1816–1875):an unknown pioneer of the mathematization of logic in england, 1839.M. Pabteki - 1993 - History and Philosophy of Logic 14 (2):133-169.
    (1993). Thomas solly (1816–1875):an unknown pioneer of the mathematization of logic in england, 1839. History and Philosophy of Logic: Vol. 14, No. 2, pp. 133-169.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A computational approach to George Boole's discovery of mathematical logic.Luis de Ledesma, Aurora Pérez, Daniel Borrajo & Luis M. Laita - 1997 - Artificial Intelligence 91 (2):281-307.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Psychology in the foundations of logic and mathematics: the cases of boole, cantor and brouwer.I. Grattan-Guinness - 1982 - History and Philosophy of Logic 3 (1):33-53.
    In this paper I consider three mathematicians who allowed some role for menial processes in the foundations of their logical or mathematical theories. Boole regarded his Boolean algebra as a theory of mental acts; Cantor permitted processes of abstraction to play a role in his set theory; Brouwer took perception in time as a cornerstone of his intuitionist mathematics. Three appendices consider related topics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Horrent with Mysterious Spiculæ’. Augustus De Morgan’s Logic Notation of 1850 as a ‘Calculus of Opposite Relations.Anna-Sophie Heinemann - 2018 - History and Philosophy of Logic 39 (1):29-52.
    The present paper expounds the logic notation proposed by Augustus De Morgan in 1850 from within the original context of De Morgan’s account of syllogistic logic and his approach to quantification. The notational system of 1850 is shown to be a flexible tool to state inferences, to prove their validity and to derive formulæ of the respective system by ‘blind’ application of transformation rules. These pertain to the swapping of operator signs, which are of inverse ‘character’ in a two-fold sense: (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The correspondence between george boole and stanley jevons, 1863–1864.I. Grattan-Guinness - 1991 - History and Philosophy of Logic 12 (1):15-35.
    Although the existence of correspondence between George Boole (1815?1864) and William Stanley Jevons (1835?1882) has been known for a long time and part was even published in 1913, it has never been fully noted; in particular, it is not in the recent edition of Jevons's letters and papers. The texts are transcribed here, with indication of their significance. Jevons proposed certain quite radical changes to Boole's system, which Boole did not accept; nevertheless, they were to become well established.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Jean van Heijenoort’s Conception of Modern Logic, in Historical Perspective.Irving H. Anellis - 2012 - Logica Universalis 6 (3):339-409.
    I use van Heijenoort’s published writings and manuscript materials to provide a comprehensive overview of his conception of modern logic as a first-order functional calculus and of the historical developments which led to this conception of mathematical logic, its defining characteristics, and in particular to provide an integral account, from his most important publications as well as his unpublished notes and scattered shorter historico-philosophical articles, of how and why the mathematical logic, whose he traced to Frege and the culmination of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • ‘Everybody makes errors’: The intersection of De Morgan's Logic and Probability, 1837 – 1847.Adrian Rice - 2003 - History and Philosophy of Logic 24 (4):289-305.
    For Ivor Grattan-Guinness on the occasion of his retirement. The work of Augustus De Morgan on symbolic logic in the mid-nineteenth century is familiar to historians of logic and mathematics alike. What is less well known is his work on probability and, more specifically, the use of probabilistic ideas and methods in his logic. The majority of De Morgan's work on probability was undertaken around 1837???1838, with his earliest publications on logic appearing from 1839, a period which culminated with the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hugh maccoll: eine bibliographische erschließung seiner hauptwerke und notizen zu ihrer rezeptionsgeschichte.Shahid Rahman - 1997 - History and Philosophy of Logic 18 (3):165-183.
    The work of Hugh MacColl (1837–1909) suffered the same fate after his death as before it:despite being vaguely alluded to and in part even commended, on the whole it has remained an unknown quantity. Even worse, those of his ideas which have played a decisive role in the history of logic have been credited to his successors; this is especially the case with the definition of strict implication and the first formal development of formal modal logic. This paper takes an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations