Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. On a Combination of Truth and Probability: Probabilistic Independence-Friendly Logic.Gabriel Sandu - 2015 - In Alexandru Manafu (ed.), The Prospects for Fusion Emergence. Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science, vol. 313: Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science, vol. 313.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Getting the constraints on Popper's probability functions right.Hugues Leblanc & Peter Roeper - 1993 - Philosophy of Science 60 (1):151-157.
    Shown here is that a constraint used by Popper in The Logic of Scientific Discovery (1959) for calculating the absolute probability of a universal quantification, and one introduced by Stalnaker in "Probability and Conditionals" (1970, 70) for calculating the relative probability of a negation, are too weak for the job. The constraint wanted in the first case is in Bendall (1979) and that wanted in the second case is in Popper (1959).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Against Harmony: Infinite Idealizations and Causal Explanation.Iulian D. Toader - 2015 - In Ilie Parvu, Gabriel Sandu & Iulian D. Toader (eds.), Romanian Studies in Philosophy of Science. Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science, vol. 313: Springer. pp. 291-301.
    This paper argues against the view that the standard explanation of phase transitions in statistical mechanics may be considered a causal explanation, a distortion that can nevertheless successfully represent causal relations.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Probability logic in the twentieth century.Theodore Hailperin - 1991 - History and Philosophy of Logic 12 (1):71-110.
    This essay describes a variety of contributions which relate to the connection of probability with logic. Some are grand attempts at providing a logical foundation for probability and inductive inference. Others are concerned with probabilistic inference or, more generally, with the transmittance of probability through the structure (logical syntax) of language. In this latter context probability is considered as a semantic notion playing the same role as does truth value in conventional logic. At the conclusion of the essay two fully (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A new semantics for first-order logic, multivalent and mostly intensional.Hugues Leblanc - 1984 - Topoi 3 (1):55-62.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Probability functions and their assumption sets — the singulary case.Hugues Leblanc - 1983 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 12 (4):379 - 402.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The autonomy of probability theory (notes on Kolmogorov, rényi, and popper).Hugues Leblanc - 1989 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 40 (2):167-181.
    Kolmogorov's account in his [1933] of an absolute probability space presupposes given a Boolean algebra, and so does Rényi's account in his [1955] and [1964] of a relative probability space. Anxious to prove probability theory ‘autonomous’. Popper supplied in his [1955] and [1957] accounts of probability spaces of which Boolean algebras are not and [1957] accounts of probability spaces of which fields are not prerequisites but byproducts instead.1 I review the accounts in question, showing how Popper's issue from and how (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Hommage à Hugues Leblanc, philosophe logicien.Robert Nadeau - 1986 - Philosophiques 13 (1):131-145.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On Characterizing Unary Probability Functions and Truth-Value Functions.Hugues Leblanc - 1985 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 15 (1):19 - 24.
    Consider a language SL having as its primitive signs one or more atomic statements, the two connectives ‘∼’ and ‘&,’ and the two parentheses ‘’; and presume the extra connectives ‘V’ and ‘≡’ defined in the customary manner. With the statements of SL substituting for sets, and the three connectives ‘∼,’ ‘&,’and ‘V’ substituting for the complementation, intersection, and union signs, the constraints that Kolmogorov places in [1] on probability functions come to read:K1. 0 ≤ P,K2. P) = 1,K3. If (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations