Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. A Theory of Philosophical Arguments.Christoph Lumer - 2020 - Evidence, Persuasion and Diversity. Proceedings of Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation Conference, Vol. 12 (2020).
    In this article, a new, idealizing-hermeneutic methodological approach to developing a theory of philosophical arguments is presented and carried out. The basis for this is a theory of ideal philosophical theory types developed from the analysis of historical examples. According to this theory, the following ideal types of theory exist in philosophy: 1. descriptive-nomological, 2. idealizing-hermeneutic, 3. technical-constructive, 4. ontic-practical. These types of theories are characterized in particular by what their basic types of theses are. The main task of this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Logic in Early Modern Thought.Katarina Peixoto & Edgar da Rocha Marques - 2020 - Encyclopedia of Early Modern Philosophy and the Sciences,.
    Logical reflection in early modern philosophy (EMP) is marked by the instability of the period, although it is more lasting (the Port-Royal Logic was nevertheless used as a handbook in philosophy courses until the end of the nineteenth century). It started in the sixteenth century and ended in the nineteenth century, a period of 300 years during which there were deep transformations in the conceptions of authority and scientific method. For the history of twentieth-century philosophy, it was the period of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Redescubriendo la lógica diagramática de Leibniz.J. Martín Castro Manzano - 2016 - Tópicos: Revista de Filosofía 52:89-116.
    En este artículo recuperamos la lógica diagramática lineal de Leibniz para la silogística y descubrimos sus propiedades lógicas y computacionales a través de una aproximación formal en términos metalógicos, lo cual es algo que, hasta donde sabemos, aún falta por hacerse. Así, en esta contribución buscamos, respectivamente, dos metas, una histórica y una lógica: i) prestar más atención a los aspectos algorítmicos del sistema diagramático lineal de Leibniz para la silogística, de los cuales creemos que han sido desdeñados por un (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Rewriting the History of Connexive Logic.Wolfgang Lenzen - 2022 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 51 (3):525-553.
    The “official” history of connexive logic was written in 2012 by Storrs McCall who argued that connexive logic was founded by ancient logicians like Aristotle, Chrysippus, and Boethius; that it was further developed by medieval logicians like Abelard, Kilwardby, and Paul of Venice; and that it was rediscovered in the 19th and twentieth century by Lewis Carroll, Hugh MacColl, Frank P. Ramsey, and Everett J. Nelson. From 1960 onwards, connexive logic was finally transformed into non-classical calculi which partly concur with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Guilielmi Pacidii Non plus ultra, oder: Eine Rekonstruktion des Leibnizschen Plus-Minus-Kalküls.Wolfgang Lenzen - 2000 - History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 3 (1):71-118.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Essay Review.Gyula Klima - 2003 - History and Philosophy of Logic 24 (2):135-140.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Essay Review.Gyula Klima - 2003 - History and Philosophy of Logic 24 (2):141-162.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Judgement in Leibniz’s Conception of the Mind: Predication, Affirmation, and Denial.Christian Barth - 2020 - Topoi (3).
    The aim of the paper is to illuminate some core aspects of Leibniz’s conception of judgement and its place in his conception of the mind. In particular, the paper argues for three claims: First, the act of judgement is at the centre of Leibniz’s conception of the mind in that minds strive at actualising innate knowledge concerning derivative truths, where the actualising involves an act of judgement. Second, Leibniz does not hold a judgement account of predication, but a two-component account (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Leibniz on intension, extension, and the representation of syllogistic inference.O. Bradley Bassler - 1998 - Synthese 116 (2):117-139.
    New light is shed on Leibniz’s commitment to the metaphysical priority of the intensional interpretation of logic by considering the arithmetical and graphical representations of syllogistic inference that Leibniz studied. Crucial to understanding this connection is the idea that concepts can be intensionally represented in terms of properties of geometric extension, though significantly not the simple geometric property of part-whole inclusion. I go on to provide an explanation for how Leibniz could maintain the metaphysical priority of the intensional interpretation while (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Inter-model connectives and substructural logics.Igor Sedlár - 2014 - In Roberto Ciuni, Heinrich Wansing & Caroline Willkommen (eds.), Recent Trends in Philosophical Logic (Proceedings of Trends in Logic XI). Cham, Switzerland: Springer. pp. 195-209.
    The paper provides an alternative interpretation of ‘pair points’, discussed in Beall et al., "On the ternary relation and conditionality", J. of Philosophical Logic 41(3), 595-612. Pair points are seen as points viewed from two different ‘perspectives’ and the latter are explicated in terms of two independent valuations. The interpretation is developed into a semantics using pairs of Kripke models (‘pair models’). It is demonstrated that, if certain conditions are fulfilled, pair models are validity-preserving copies of positive substructural models. This (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation