Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Methodological problems in evolutionary biology IV. Stress and stress tolerance, an excercise in definitions.Wim J. Van der Steen & Martin Scholten - 1985 - Acta Biotheoretica 34 (1):81-90.
    Grime in a recently developed theory distinguished three basic plant strategies: stress tolerance,ruderality and competition. He relates them to environments characterized in terms of stress and disturbance. Classifications of strategies and environments both are ultimately defined in terms of production. This tends to make the theory tautological. If the theory is to make sense, environments had better be defined in independent terms.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Aggression and violence around the world: A model of CLimate, Aggression, and Self-control in Humans.Paul A. M. Van Lange, Maria I. Rinderu & Brad J. Bushman - 2017 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 40:1-63.
    Worldwide there are substantial differences within and between countries in aggression and violence. Although there are various exceptions, a general rule is that aggression and violence increase as one moves closer to the equator, which suggests the important role of climate differences. While this pattern is robust, theoretical explanations for these large differences in aggression and violence within countries and around the world are lacking. Most extant explanations focus on the influence of average temperature as a factor that triggers aggression, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Love Styles in the Context of Life History Theory.Andrzej Łukasik & Magdalena Marzec - 2017 - Polish Psychological Bulletin 48 (2):237-249.
    The evolutionary function of love is to create a strong bond between the partners with reproduction in view. In order to achieve this goal, humans use various sexual/reproductive strategies, which have evolved due to specific reproductive benefits. The use of particular strategies depends on many factors but one of the most important is early childhood experiences, on which life history theory focuses. John Lee identified 6 basic love styles: eros, ludus, storge, pragma, agape, and mania. Our goal was to check (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Tale of Two Regimes: Instrumentality and Commons Access.Noah J. Toly - 2005 - Bulletin of Science, Technology and Society 25 (1):26-36.
    Technical developments have profound social and environmental impacts. Both are observed in the implications of regimes of instrumentality for commons access regimes. Establishing social, material, ecological, intellectual, and moral infrastructures, technologies are partly constitutive of commons access and may militate against governance according to principles of ecological justice. This article examines the relationship between regimes of instrumentality and commons access regimes, exploring the effects of bioprospecting on the biodiversity commons.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Genetic consequences of variation in sib maturation schedules.Barbara L. Thorne - 1981 - Acta Biotheoretica 30 (4):219-227.
    Implications of variance in the time at which sibs become mature are considered, particularly with respect to the fragmentation of a parental genome over time. It is concluded that regardless of the adaptive derivation of various intra-sibship maturation schedules, they each have important genetic consequences.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sexual momentum may be independent of social status.Del Thiessen - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):308-309.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Environmental tracking by females.Del Thiessen - 1994 - Human Nature 5 (2):167-202.
    Human females are generally reserved in their sexuality, in keeping with their heavy investment in reproduction. Males tend to be less reserved. Relative to males, however, females demonstrate more variability in sexuality and are more likely to inhibit or express high levels of sexuality. The heightened variability may in part originate with genetic mechanisms that predispose females toward greater variability. Menarche, menstrual cycles, menopause, food reactions, responses to living conditions, reactions to cultural factors, and responses to sexual stimuli and potential (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Null hypotheses in ecology.Donald R. Strong - 1980 - Synthese 43 (2):271-285.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • “Potential” reproductions as an alternative proxy for reproductive success: A great direction, but the wrong road.David C. Steven - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):307-308.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cultural versus reproductive success: Resolving the conundrum.Eric Alden Smith - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):307-307.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A contribution to the geographical interpretation of biological change.Charles H. Smith - 1986 - Acta Biotheoretica 35 (4):229-278.
    Geography has traditionally been assigned the role of handmaiden in evolutionary studies. In this work a different understanding of the relationship between biological change and locational setting is developed: evolution as a dynamic form of spatial interaction. In the causal model presented, adaptive change is portrayed as a negative feedback response contributing to a general spatial-temporal process of resource cycle tightening involving exchanges between the two fundamental structural sectors (abiotic and biotic) of the earth's surface system. As such, it is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Anchoring in Ecosystemic Kinds.Matthew H. Slater - 2018 - Synthese 195 (4):1487-1508.
    The world contains many different types of ecosystems. This is something of a commonplace in biology and conservation science. But there has been little attention to the question of whether such ecosystem types enjoy a degree of objectivity—whether they might be natural kinds. I argue that traditional accounts of natural kinds that emphasize nomic or causal–mechanistic dimensions of “kindhood” are ill-equipped to accommodate presumptive ecosystemic kinds. In particular, unlike many other kinds, ecosystemic kinds are “anchored” to the contingent character of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Male reproductive success as a function of social status: Some unanswered evolutionary questions.Jeffry A. Simpson - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):305-307.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The adaptiveness of imaginatively eliminating behaviors: Stripping the cultural varnish from the natural evolutionary woodwork.James Silverberg - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):304-305.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Non-indigenous species and ecological explanation.Kristin Shrader-Frechette - 2001 - Biology and Philosophy 16 (4):507-519.
    Within the last 20 years, the US has mounted amassive campaign against invasions bynon-indigenous species (NIS) such as zebramussels, kudzu, water hyacinths, and brown treesnakes. NIS have disrupted native ecosystemsand caused hundreds of billions of dollars ofannual damage. Many in the scientificcommunity say the problem of NIS is primarilypolitical and economic: getting governments toregulate powerful vested interests thatintroduce species through such vehicles asships' ballast water. This paper argues that,although politics and economics play a role,the problem is primarily one of scientificmethod. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • An ecological theory of learning: Good goal, poor strategy.Sara J. Shettleworth - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):160-161.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Island Biogeography and the Multiple Domains of Models.Sismondo Sergio - 2000 - Biology and Philosophy 15 (2):239-258.
    This paper adopts a symmetrical approach tocontroversies over R.H. MacArthur and E.O. Wilson'sequilibrium model of island biogeography, in order toshow how different interpretations of the model dependupon different philosophical understandings of theapplication of models and theories. In particular,there are quite distinct domains to which the modelcould apply; in addition, some equivocation amongthese domains is important to the model's success.Therefore, apparently inconsistent interpretations,interpretations that fit into roughly instrumentalist,realist and rationalist conceptions of science, may bemutually supporting in practice. Descriptions ofscientific practice, then, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Stephen Jay Gould, Jack Sepkoski, and the ‘Quantitative Revolution’ in American Paleobiology.David Sepkoski - 2005 - Journal of the History of Biology 38 (2):209-237.
    During the 1970s, a "revolution" in American paleobiology took place. It came about in part because a group of mostly young, ambitious paleontologists adapted many of the quantitative methodologies and techniques developed in fields including biology and ecology over the previous several decades to their own discipline. Stephen Jay Gould, who was then just beginning his career, joined others in articulating a singular vision for transforming paleontology from an isolated and often ignored science to a "nomothetic discipline" that could sit (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Colleagues in conflict: An 'in vivo' analysis of the sociobiology controversy. [REVIEW]Ullica Segerstrale - 1986 - Biology and Philosophy 1 (1):53-87.
    Edward O. Wilson's forays into human sociobiology have been the target of persistent, vehement attack by his Harvard colleague in evolutionary biology, Richard C. Lewontin. Through examination of existing documents in the case, together with in-depth personal interviews of Wilson, Lewontin, and other biologists, the reasons for Wilson's stance and Lewontin's criticisms are uncovered. It is argued that the dispute is not primarily personally or politically motivated, but involves a conflict between long-term scientific-cum-moral agendas, with the reductionist program as a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • The ecology of learning: The right answer to the wrong question.Barry Schwartz - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):159-160.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Beyond the Hype: The Value of Evolutionary Theorizing in Economics.Armin W. Schulz - 2013 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 43 (1):46-72.
    In this paper, I consider the recent resurgence of “evolutionary economics”—the idea that evolutionary theory can be very useful to push forward key debates in economics—and assess the extent to which it rests on a plausible foundation. To do this, I first distinguish two ways in which evolutionary theory can, in principle, be brought to bear on an economic problem—namely, evidentially and heuristically—and then apply this distinction to the three major hypotheses that evolutionary economists have come to defend: the implausibility (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Adaptive modification of behavior: Processing information from the environment.Wolfgang M. Schleidt - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):158-159.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Complementarity and the selection of nature reserves: algorithms and the origins of conservation planning, 1980–1995.Sahotra Sarkar - 2012 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 66 (4):397-426.
    This paper reconstructs the history of the introduction and use of iterative algorithms in conservation biology in the 1980s and early 1990s in order to prioritize areas for protection as nature reserves. The importance of these algorithms was that they led to greater economy in spatial extent (“efficiency”) in the selection of areas to represent biological features adequately (that is, to a specified level) compared to older methods of scoring and ranking areas using criteria such as biotic “richness” (the number (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Biodiversity is a chimera, and chimeras aren’t real.Carlos Santana - 2018 - Biology and Philosophy 33 (1-2):15.
    A recent article by Burch-Brown and Archer provides compelling arguments that biodiversity is either a natural kind or a pragmatically-valid scientific entity. I call into question three of these arguments. The first argument contends that biodiversity is a Homeostatic Property Cluster. I respond that there is no plausible homeostatic mechanism that would make biodiversity an HPC natural kind. The second argument proposes that biodiversity is a multiply-realizable functional kind. I respond that there is no shared function to ground this account. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • On the Definition of Ecology.Mark Sagoff - 2017 - Biological Theory 12 (2):85-98.
    In this article I discuss the proposition that ecologists may place restrictions on the kinds of plants and animals and on the kinds of systems they consider relevant to assessing the resiliency of ecological generalizations. I argue that to restrict the extension of ecological science and its concepts in order to exclude cultivated plants, captive animals, and domesticated environments ecologists must appeal either to the boundaries of their discipline; to the idea that the effects of human activity are rare and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Explaining diversity and searching for general processes: Isn't there a middle ground?Paul Rozin - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):157-158.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Known general principles of learning cannot be ignored.Sam Revusky - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):156-157.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Existence, Uniqueness, and Input-to-State Stability of Ground State Stationary Strong Solution of a Single-Species Model via Mountain Pass Lemma.Ruofeng Rao, Quanxin Zhu & Jialin Huang - 2021 - Complexity 2021:1-11.
    In this study, the authors utilize mountain pass lemma, variational methods, regularization technique, and the Lyapunov function method to derive the unique existence of the positive classical stationary solution of a single-species ecosystem. Particularly, the geometric characteristic of saddle point in the mountain pass lemma guarantees that the equilibrium point is the ground state stationary solution of the ecosystem. Based on the obtained uniqueness result, the authors use the Lyapunov function method to derive the globally exponential stability criterion, which illuminates (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Stability and lawlikeness.Jani Raerinne - 2013 - Biology and Philosophy 28 (5):833-851.
    There appear to be no biological regularities that have the properties traditionally associated with laws, such as an unlimited scope or holding in all or many possible background conditions. Mitchell, Lange, and others have therefore suggested redefining laws to redeem the lawlike status of biological regularities. These authors suggest that biological regularities are lawlike because they are pragmatically or paradigmatically similar to laws or stable regularities. I will review these re-definitions by arguing both that there are difficulties in applying their (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Learning theory in its niche.Howard Rachlin - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):155-156.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Kin Selection and Its Discontents.David C. Queller - 2016 - Philosophy of Science 83 (5):861-872.
    Kin selection is a core aspect of social evolution theory, but a small number of critics have recently challenged it. Here I address these criticisms and show that kin selection remains an important explanation for much social evolution. I show how many of the criticisms rest on historical idiosyncrasies of the way the field happened to develop, rather than on the real logic and evidence.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The mechanistic approach of The Theory of Island Biogeography and its current relevance.Viorel Pâslaru - 2014 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 45 (1):22-33.
    Philosophers of science have examined The Theory of Island Biogeography by Robert MacArthur and E. O. Wilson (1967) mainly due to its important contribution to modeling in ecology, but they have not examined it as a representative case of ecological explanation. In this paper, I scrutinize the type of explanation used in this paradigmatic work of ecology. I describe the philosophy of science of MacArthur and Wilson and show that it is mechanistic. Based on this account and in light of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Human status seeking is a Darwinian adaptation.Daniel Pérusse - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):312-322.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Cultural and reproductive success in industrial societies: Testing the relationship at the proximate and ultimate levels.Daniel Pérusse - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):267-283.
    In most social species, position in the male social hierarchy and reproductive success are positively correlated; in humans, however, this relationship is less clear, with studies of traditional societies yielding mixed results. In the most economically advanced human populations, the adaptiveness of status vanishes altogether; social status and fertility are uncorrelated. These findings have been interpreted to suggest that evolutionary principles may not be appropriate for the explanation of human behavior, especially in modern environments. The present study tests the adaptiveness (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   106 citations  
  • Stretching the theory beyond its limits.H. C. Plotkin - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):303-304.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is an ecological approach radical enough?H. C. Plotkin & F. J. Odling-Smee - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):154-155.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • A functional view of learning.Lewis Petrinovich - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):153-154.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The strategy of “the strategy of model building in population biology”.Jay Odenbaugh - 2006 - Biology and Philosophy 21 (5):607-621.
    In this essay, I argue for four related claims. First, Richard Levins’ classic “The Strategy of Model Building in Population Biology” was a statement and defense of theoretical population biology growing out of collaborations between Robert MacArthur, Richard Lewontin, E. O. Wilson, and others. Second, I argue that the essay served as a response to the rise of systems ecology especially as pioneered by Kenneth Watt. Third, the arguments offered by Levins against systems ecology and in favor of his own (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Learning theory: Behavioral artifacts or general principles?John A. Nevin - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):152-153.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Entities on a Temporal Scale.Christopher M. Murray & Brian I. Crother - 2015 - Acta Biotheoretica 64 (1):1-10.
    Ontological understanding of biological units is crucial to their use in experimental design, analysis, and interpretation. Conceptualizing fundamental units in biology as individuals or classes is important for subsequent development of discovery operations. While the criteria for diagnosing individuals are acknowledged, temporal boundedness is often misinterpreted and temporal minima are applied to units in question. This results in misdiagnosis or abandonment of ontological interpretation altogether. Biological units such as areas of endemism in biogeography and species in evolutionary biology fall victim (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Owls, Climates, and Experts.Robert L. Munroe & Mary Gauvain - 2018 - Journal of Cognition and Culture 18 (1-2):66-88.
    The cognitive research of Atran and Medin plus preliminary cross-cultural inquiry about owls permitted the formulation of a hypothesis: Inhabitants of cold-climate societies were likely to be, in relative terms, “experts” on owls. Subsequent cross-cultural study affirmed that in cold-climate societies, in contrast to others, the habits and characteristics of owls were more frequently noted, these birds were more often used functionally, and the human inhabitants of cold-climate areas manifested fewer negative supernaturalistic interpretations of owl behavior. For the sample as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cultural success and the study of adaptive design.Monique Borgerhoff Mulder - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):286-287.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Actual and potential reproduction: There is no substitute for victory.Ulrich Mueller - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):301-303.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Neutral and niche theory in community ecology: a framework for comparing model realism.Katie H. Morrow - 2024 - Biology and Philosophy 39 (1):1-19.
    Ecological neutral theory has been controversial as an alternative to niche theory for explaining community structure. Neutral theory, which explains community structure in terms of ecological drift, is frequently charged with being unrealistic, but commentators have usually not provided an account of theory or model realism. In this paper, I propose a framework for comparing the “realism” or accuracy of alternative theories within a domain with respect to the extent to which the theories abstract and idealize. Using this framework I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Matthew’s (1915) climate and evolution, the “New York School of Biogeography”, and the rise and fall of “Holarcticism”.Juan J. Morrone - 2022 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 44 (2):1-27.
    Climate and evolution represents an important contribution to evolutionary biogeography, that influenced several authors, notably Karl P. Schmidt, George S. Myers, George G. Simpson, Philip J. Darlington, Ernst Mayr, Thomas Barbour, John C. Poynton, Allen Keast, Léon Croizat, Robin Craw, Michael Heads, and Osvaldo A. Reig. Authors belonging to the “New York School of Zoogeography” –a research community including Matthew, Schmidt, Myers and Simpson– accepted Matthew’s “Holarcticism” and the permanence of ocean basins and continents, whereas others, especially panbiogeographers and cladistic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Plant succession and tree architecture: An attempt at reconciling two scales of analysis of vegetation dynamics.Jeanne Millet, André Bouchard & Claude Édelin - 1998 - Acta Biotheoretica 46 (1):1-22.
    Plant succession is a phenomenon ascribed to vegetation dynamics at the scale of the plant community. The study of plant succession implies the analysis of the species involved and their relationships. Depending on the research done, the characteristics of trees have been studied according to either static, dimensional or partial approaches. We have revised the principal theories of succession, the methods of describing structure and development of tree and relationship established between tree species' attributes and their successional status. During studies (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Exploring the Status of Population Genetics: The Role of Ecology.Roberta L. Millstein - 2013 - Biological Theory 7 (4):346-357.
    The status of population genetics has become hotly debated among biologists and philosophers of biology. Many seem to view population genetics as relatively unchanged since the Modern Synthesis and have argued that subjects such as development were left out of the Synthesis. Some have called for an extended evolutionary synthesis or for recognizing the insignificance of population genetics. Yet others such as Michael Lynch have defended population genetics, declaring "nothing in evolution makes sense except in the light of population genetics" (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Methods and Metaphors in Community Ecology: The Problem of Defining Stability.Gregory M. Mikkelson - 1997 - Perspectives on Science 5 (4):481-498.
    Scientists must sometimes choose between competing definitions of key terms. The degree to which different definitions facilitate important discoveries should ultimately guide decisions about which terms to accept. In the short run, rules of thumb can help. One such rule is to regard with suspicion any definition that turns a seemingly important empirical matter into an a priori exercise. Several prominent definitions of ecological “stability” are suspect, according to this rule. After evaluating alternatives, I suggest that the faulty definitions resulted (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Carlquist revisited: history, success, and applicability of a natural history model.Stephen R. Midway & Anne-Marie C. Hodge - 2012 - Biology and Philosophy 27 (4):497-520.
    In 1966, island biogeographer Sherwin Carlquist published a list of 24 principles governing long-distance dispersal and evolution on islands. The 24 principles describe many aspects of island biology, from long-distance dispersal and establishment to community change and assemblage. Although this was an active period for island biogeography, other models and research garnered much more attention than did Carlquist’s. In this review, over 40 years of support for or against Carlquist’s principles is presented. Recent work has supported most of the 24 (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Towards a unified science of cultural evolution.Alex Mesoudi, Andrew Whiten & Kevin N. Laland - 2006 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 29 (4):329-347.
    We suggest that human culture exhibits key Darwinian evolutionary properties, and argue that the structure of a science of cultural evolution should share fundamental features with the structure of the science of biological evolution. This latter claim is tested by outlining the methods and approaches employed by the principal subdisciplines of evolutionary biology and assessing whether there is an existing or potential corresponding approach to the study of cultural evolution. Existing approaches within anthropology and archaeology demonstrate a good match with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   85 citations