Switch to: References

Citations of:

Studies in the Hegelian Dialectic

Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press (1896)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Dialectic and argument in philosophy: A case study of Hegel's phenomenological preface. [REVIEW]MauriceA Finocchiaro - 1988 - Argumentation 2 (2):175-190.
    This article examines two problems: the role of argument in philosophy, vis-àÏs other philosophical activities; and the nature of argument in philosophy, vis-à-vis argument in other fields. The examination proceeds by reference to the notion of dialectic, which is regarded by some as offering an alternative to argument, and by reference to Hegel's Preface to the Phenomenology of Spirit, which explicitly discusses these very issues. The latter is reconstructed as the argument that philosophy is dialectical in part because it is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dialetheism.Francesco Berto, Graham Priest & Zach Weber - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2018 (2018).
    A dialetheia is a sentence, A, such that both it and its negation, ¬A, are true (we shall talk of sentences throughout this entry; but one could run the definition in terms of propositions, statements, or whatever one takes as her favourite truth-bearer: this would make little difference in the context). Assuming the fairly uncontroversial view that falsity just is the truth of negation, it can equally be claimed that a dialetheia is a sentence which is both true and false.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   72 citations  
  • Hegel, Spinoza, and McTaggart on the Reality of Time.Yitzhak Melamed - 2016 - Internationales Jahrbuch des Deutschen Idealismus / International Yearbook of German Idealism 14:211-234.
    In this paper, I study one aspect of the philosophical encounter between Spinoza and Hegel: the question of the reality of time. The precise reconstruction of the debate will require a close examination of Spinoza's concept of tempus (time) and duratio (duration), and Hegel's understanding of these notions. Following a presentation of Hegel's perception of Spinoza as a modern Eleatic, who denies the reality of time, change and plurality, I turn, in the second part, to look closely at Spinoza's text (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Transcendence and Non-Contradiction.Simon Skempton - 2016 - Journal of Philosophical Research 41:17-42.
    This article is an inquiry into how the relationship between the principle of non-contradiction and the limits of thought has been understood by thinkers as diverse as Hegel, Heidegger, Levinas, and Graham Priest. While Heidegger and Levinas focus on the question of temporality and Priest takes a formal approach, all these philosophers effectively maintain that the principle of non-contradiction imposes a restriction on thought that disables it from adequately accounting for its own limits and thus what lies beyond those limits, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dialetheism.Graham Priest - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    A dialetheia is a sentence, A, such that both it and its negation, A, are true (we shall talk of sentences throughout this entry; but one could run the definition in terms of propositions, statements, or whatever one takes as her favourite truth bearer: this would make little difference in the context). Assuming the fairly uncontroversial view that falsity just is the truth of negation, it can equally be claimed that a dialetheia is a sentence which is both true and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Hegel, contradicción Y dialetheia.Rafael Miranda Rojas - 2013 - Revista de filosofía (Chile) 69:169-181.
    This paper discusses how Hegel understands the principle of contradiction. It is analysed, first, the way Aristotle understands this principle, emphasizing the so called semantic and ontological readings. Then, it is analysed whether it is correct to argue that Hegel rejects this principle, holding here that, strictly speaking, this is not correct. To do this, we present a dialetheist reading of Hegelian logic, which allows to state that: i) Hegel does not accept trivialism and, from i), ii) is not feasible (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The eclecticism as programme: philosophy and science in Europe in the second half of the nineteenth century.Henrique Jales Ribeiro - 2013 - Revista Filosófica de Coimbra 22 (43):123-141.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Some Limits To Hegel's Appeal to Life.Andrew Werner - 2019 - Argumenta 8:143-157.
    For two hundred years, people have been trying to make sense of Hegel’s so-called “dialectical method”. Helpfully, Hegel frequently compares this method with the idea of life, or the organic (cf., e.g., PhG 2, 34, 56). This comparison has become very popular in the literature (in, e.g., Pippin, Beiser, and Ng). Typically, scholars who invoke the idea of life also note that the comparison has limits and that no organic analogy can completely explain the nature of the dialectical method. To (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • From the bankruptcy of relations to the reality of connections: language and semantics in Bradley and Bosanquet.Guillaume Lejeune - 2018 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 26 (4):700-718.
    . From the bankruptcy of relations to the reality of connections: language and semantics in Bradley and Bosanquet. British Journal for the History of Philosophy: Vol. 26, Special Issue: British Idealism: Language, Aesthetics and Emotions. Guest Editors: Colin Tyler and James Connelly, pp. 700-718.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Religious Epistemology and Dialectic.Muhammad Legenhausen - 2019 - Journal of Philosophical Theological Research 21 (3):43-58.
    Much recent discussion of the epistemology of religious belief has focused on justification of belief in the existence of God. Religious belief, however, includes much more than belief in God. In this paper, it is argued that the justification of belief in God is best seen in the context of other interrelated religious beliefs and practices. Philosophers of religion argue about whether religious belief requires evidence and on the sorts of arguments that have been presented. In this paper, a dialectical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark