Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. How much randomness is needed for statistics?Bjørn Kjos-Hanssen, Antoine Taveneaux & Neil Thapen - 2014 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 165 (9):1470-1483.
    In algorithmic randomness, when one wants to define a randomness notion with respect to some non-computable measure λ, a choice needs to be made. One approach is to allow randomness tests to access the measure λ as an oracle. The other approach is the opposite one, where the randomness tests are completely effective and do not have access to the information contained in λ. While the Hippocratic approach is in general much more restrictive, there are cases where the two coincide. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kolmogorov–Loveland randomness and stochasticity.Wolfgang Merkle, Joseph S. Miller, André Nies, Jan Reimann & Frank Stephan - 2006 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 138 (1):183-210.
    An infinite binary sequence X is Kolmogorov–Loveland random if there is no computable non-monotonic betting strategy that succeeds on X in the sense of having an unbounded gain in the limit while betting successively on bits of X. A sequence X is KL-stochastic if there is no computable non-monotonic selection rule that selects from X an infinite, biased sequence.One of the major open problems in the field of effective randomness is whether Martin-Löf randomness is the same as KL-randomness. Our first (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Computable randomness and betting for computable probability spaces.Jason Rute - 2016 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 62 (4-5):335-366.
    Unlike Martin‐Löf randomness and Schnorr randomness, computable randomness has not been defined, except for a few ad hoc cases, outside of Cantor space. This paper offers such a definition (actually, several equivalent definitions), and further, provides a general method for abstracting “bit‐wise” definitions of randomness from Cantor space to arbitrary computable probability spaces. This same method is also applied to give machine characterizations of computable and Schnorr randomness for computable probability spaces, extending the previously known results. The paper contains a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Polynomial clone reducibility.Quinn Culver - 2014 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 53 (1-2):1-10.
    Polynomial clone reducibilities are generalizations of the truth-table reducibilities. A polynomial clone is a set of functions over a finite set X that is closed under composition and contains all the constant and projection functions. For a fixed polynomial clone ${\fancyscript{C}}$ , a sequence ${B\in X^{\omega}}$ is ${\fancyscript{C}}$ -reducible to ${A \in {X}^{\omega}}$ if there is an algorithm that computes B from A using only effectively selected functions from ${\fancyscript{C}}$ . We show that if A is Kurtz random and ${\fancyscript{C}_{1} (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How much randomness is needed for statistics?Bjørn Kjos-Hanssen, Antoine Taveneaux & Neil Thapen - 2012 - In S. Barry Cooper (ed.), How the World Computes. pp. 395--404.
    In algorithmic randomness, when one wants to define a randomness notion with respect to some non-computable measure λ, a choice needs to be made. One approach is to allow randomness tests to access the measure λ as an oracle . The other approach is the opposite one, where the randomness tests are completely effective and do not have access to the information contained in λ . While the Hippocratic approach is in general much more restrictive, there are cases where the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Constructive equivalence relations on computable probability measures.Laurent Bienvenu & Wolfgang Merkle - 2009 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 160 (3):238-254.
    A central object of study in the field of algorithmic randomness are notions of randomness for sequences, i.e., infinite sequences of zeros and ones. These notions are usually defined with respect to the uniform measure on the set of all sequences, but extend canonically to other computable probability measures. This way each notion of randomness induces an equivalence relation on the computable probability measures where two measures are equivalent if they have the same set of random sequences. In what follows, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Uniform distribution and algorithmic randomness.Jeremy Avigad - 2013 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 78 (1):334-344.
    A seminal theorem due to Weyl [14] states that if $(a_n)$ is any sequence of distinct integers, then, for almost every $x \in \mathbb{R}$, the sequence $(a_n x)$ is uniformly distributed modulo one. In particular, for almost every $x$ in the unit interval, the sequence $(a_n x)$ is uniformly distributed modulo one for every computable sequence $(a_n)$ of distinct integers. Call such an $x$ UD random. Here it is shown that every Schnorr random real is UD random, but there are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations