Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. On Identity Statements: In Defense of a Sui Generis View.Tristan Haze - 2016 - Disputatio 8 (43):269-293.
    This paper is about the meaning and function of identity statements involving proper names. There are two prominent views on this topic, according to which identity statements ascribe a relation: the object-view, on which identity statements ascribe a relation borne by all objects to themselves, and the name-view, on which an identity statement 'a is b' says that the names 'a' and 'b' codesignate. The object- and name-views may seem to exhaust the field. I make a case for treating identity (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Is being Hispanic an identity? Reflections on J. J. E. Gracia’s account.Jorge Garcia - 2001 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 27 (2):29-43.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Sentence-relativity and the necessary a posteriori.Kai-Yee Wong - 1996 - Philosophical Studies 83 (1):53 - 91.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • What's Puzzling Gottlob Frege?Mike Thau & Ben Caplan - 2001 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 31 (2):159-200.
    By any reasonable reckoning, Gottlob Frege's ‘On Sense and Reference’ is one of the more important philosophical papers of all time. Although Frege briefly discusses the sense-reference distinction in an earlier work, it is through ‘Sense and Reference’ that most philosophers have become familiar with it. And the distinction so thoroughly permeates contemporary philosophy of language and mind that it is almost impossible to imagine these subjects without it.The distinction between the sense and the referent of a name is introduced (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Could God Become Man?Richard Swinburne - 1989 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lecture Series 25:53-70.
    The central doctrine of Christianity is that God intervened in human history in the person of Jesus Christ in a unique way; and that quickly became understood as the doctrine that in Jesus Christ God became man. In AD 451 the Council of Chalcedon formulated that doctrine in a precise way utilizing the current philosophical terminology, which provided a standard for the orthodoxy of subsequent thought on this issue. It affirmed its belief in ‘our Lord Jesus Christ, … truly God (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The absolutist theory of omnipotence.Nick Trakakis - 1997 - Sophia 36 (2):55-78.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Schmidentity and informativity.Hannes Fraissler - 2020 - Synthese 198 (10):9963-9989.
    Although Kripke’s œuvre has had a major impact on analytic philosophy and nearly every aspect of his studies has been thoroughly examined, this does not hold for his schmidentity argument, which, so far, has been widely neglected. To the extent to which it has been treated at all, it has been for the most part radically misunderstood. I hold that this argument, in its correctly reconstructed form, has general relevance for a treatment of Frege’s Puzzle and points towards a fundamental (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (2 other versions)Could God Become Man?Richard Swinburne - 1989 - Philosophy 25 (Supplement):53 - 70.
    Christian orthodoxy has maintained that in Jesus Christ God became man, i.e., acquired a human nature, while remaining God. Given two not unreasonable restrictions on the understanding of "man," that claim is perfectly coherent. But if the New Testament is correct in claiming that in some sense Christ was ignorant, weak, and temptable, we have to suppose that Christ had a divided mind; or, in traditional terminology, that the two natures did not totally interpenetrate.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations