Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Every polynomial-time 1-degree collapses if and only if P = PSPACE.Stephen A. Fenner, Stuart A. Kurtz & James S. Royer - 2004 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 69 (3):713-741.
    A set A is m-reducible to B if and only if there is a polynomial-time computable function f such that, for all x, x∈ A if and only if f ∈ B. Two sets are: 1-equivalent if and only if each is m-reducible to the other by one-one reductions; p-invertible equivalent if and only if each is m-reducible to the other by one-one, polynomial-time invertible reductions; and p-isomorphic if and only if there is an m-reduction from one set to the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Myhill's work in recursion theory.J. C. E. Dekker & E. Ellentuck - 1992 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 56 (1-3):43-71.
    In this paper we discuss the following contributions to recursion theory made by John Myhill: two sets are recursively isomorphic iff they are one-one equivalent; two sets are recursively isomorphic iff they are recursively equivalent and their complements are also recursively equivalent; every two creative sets are recursively isomorphic; the recursive analogue of the Cantor–Bernstein theorem; the notion of a combinatorial function and its use in the theory of recursive equivalence types.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Discontinuity Problem.Vasco Brattka - 2023 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 88 (3):1191-1212.
    Matthias Schröder has asked the question whether there is a weakest discontinuous problem in the topological version of the Weihrauch lattice. Such a problem can be considered as the weakest unsolvable problem. We introduce the discontinuity problem, and we show that it is reducible exactly to the effectively discontinuous problems, defined in a suitable way. However, in which sense this answers Schröder’s question sensitively depends on the axiomatic framework that is chosen, and it is a positive answer if we work (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Classifying positive equivalence relations.Claudio Bernardi & Andrea Sorbi - 1983 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 48 (3):529-538.
    Given two (positive) equivalence relations ∼ 1 , ∼ 2 on the set ω of natural numbers, we say that ∼ 1 is m-reducible to ∼ 2 if there exists a total recursive function h such that for every x, y ∈ ω, we have $x \sim_1 y \operatorname{iff} hx \sim_2 hy$ . We prove that the equivalence relation induced in ω by a positive precomplete numeration is complete with respect to this reducibility (and, moreover, a "uniformity property" holds). This (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Elementary theories and hereditary undecidability for semilattices of numberings.Nikolay Bazhenov, Manat Mustafa & Mars Yamaleev - 2019 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 58 (3-4):485-500.
    A major theme in the study of degree structures of all types has been the question of the decidability or undecidability of their first order theories. This is a natural and fundamental question that is an important goal in the analysis of these structures. In this paper, we study decidability for theories of upper semilattices that arise from the theory of numberings. We use the following approach: given a level of complexity, say \, we consider the upper semilattice \ of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On computable numberings of families of Turing degrees.Marat Faizrahmanov - forthcoming - Archive for Mathematical Logic:1-14.
    In this work, we study computable families of Turing degrees introduced and first studied by Arslanov and their numberings. We show that there exist finite families of Turing c.e. degrees both those with and without computable principal numberings and that every computable principal numbering of a family of Turing degrees is complete with respect to any element of the family. We also show that every computable family of Turing degrees has a complete with respect to each of its elements computable (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Splinters of recursive functions.J. S. Ullian - 1960 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 25 (1):33-38.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Note on a system of Myhill.J. C. Shepherdson - 1956 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 21 (3):261-264.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • R. e. presented linear orders.Dev Kumar Roy - 1983 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 48 (2):369-376.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Extensions of the constructive ordinals.Wayne Richter - 1965 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 30 (2):193-211.
    Kleene [5] mentions two ways of extending the constructive ordinals. The first is by relativizing the setOof notations for the constructive ordinals, using fundamental sequences which are partial recursive inO. In this way we obtain the setOOwhich provides notations for the ordinals less than ω1O. Continuing the process, the sequenceO,OO,, … and the corresponding ordinalsare obtained. A second possibility is to define higher number classes in which partial recursive functions are used at limit ordinals to provide an “accessibility” mapping from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Constructively accessible ordinal numbers.Wayne Richter - 1968 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 33 (1):43-55.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Recursion theory on orderings. II.J. B. Remmel - 1980 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 45 (2):317-333.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Recursion theory on algebraic structures with independent sets.J. B. Remmel - 1980 - Annals of Mathematical Logic 18 (2):153.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Effectively extensible theories.Marian Boykan Pour-El - 1968 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 33 (1):56-68.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • A Recursion‐theoretic View of Axiomatizable Theories.Marian Boykan Pour-El - 1970 - Dialectica 24 (4):267-276.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kleene's amazing second recursion theorem.Yiannis N. Moschovakis - 2010 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 16 (2):189 - 239.
    This little gem is stated unbilled and proved in the last two lines of §2 of the short note Kleene [1938]. In modern notation, with all the hypotheses stated explicitly and in a strong form, it reads as follows:Second Recursion Theorem. Fix a set V ⊆ ℕ, and suppose that for each natural number n ϵ ℕ = {0, 1, 2, …}, φn: ℕ1+n ⇀ V is a recursive partial function of arguments with values in V so that the standard (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Creativeness and completeness in recursion categories of partial recursive operators.Franco Montagna & Andrea Sorbi - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (3):1023-1041.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A generalisation of productive set.R. Mitchell - 1966 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 31 (3):455-459.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Recursion theory on orderings. I. a model theoretic setting.G. Metakides & J. B. Remmel - 1979 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 44 (3):383-402.
    In [6], Metakides and Nerode introduced the study of the lattice of recursively enumerable substructures of a recursively presented model as a means to understand the recursive content of certain algebraic constructions. For example, the lattice of recursively enumerable subspaces,, of a recursively presented vector spaceV∞has been studied by Kalantari, Metakides and Nerode, Retzlaff, Remmel and Shore. Similar studies have been done by Remmel [12], [13] for Boolean algebras and by Metakides and Nerode [9] for algebraically closed fields. In all (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Bounded enumeration reducibility and its degree structure.Daniele Marsibilio & Andrea Sorbi - 2012 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 51 (1-2):163-186.
    We study a strong enumeration reducibility, called bounded enumeration reducibility and denoted by ≤be, which is a natural extension of s-reducibility ≤s. We show that ≤s, ≤be, and enumeration reducibility do not coincide on the \documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${\Pi^0_1}$$\end{document} –sets, and the structure \documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${\boldsymbol{\mathcal{D}_{\rm be}}}$$\end{document} of the be-degrees is not elementarily equivalent to the structure of the s-degrees. We show also that the first order theory (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On the expressiveness of choice quantification.Bas Luttik - 2003 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 121 (1):39-87.
    We define process algebras with a generalised operation ∑ for choice. For every infinite cardinal κ, we prove that the algebra of transition trees with branching degree <κ is free in the class of process algebras in which ∑ is defined for all subsets with a cardinality <κ. We explain how the expressions of a fragment of the specification language μCRL may be used to denote elements of our process algebras. In particular, we explain how choice quantifiers may be used (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the indexing of classes of recursively enumerable sets.A. H. Lachlan - 1966 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 31 (1):10-22.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Quantifying over propositions in relevance logic: nonaxiomatisability of primary interpretations of ∀ p_ and ∃ _p.Philip Kremer - 1993 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 58 (1):334-349.
    A typical approach to semantics for relevance (and other) logics: specify a class of algebraic structures and take amodelto be one of these structures, α, together with some function or relation which associates with every formulaAa subset ofα. (This is the approach of, among others, Urquhart, Routley and Meyer and Fine.) In some cases there are restrictions on the class of subsets of α with which a formula can be associated: for example, in the semantics of Routley and Meyer [1973], (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Classes bounded by incomplete sets.Kejia Ho & Frank Stephan - 2002 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 116 (1-3):273-295.
    We study connections between strong reducibilities and properties of computably enumerable sets such as simplicity. We say that a class of computably enumerable sets bounded iff there is an m-incomplete computably enumerable set A such that every set in is m-reducible to A. For example, we show that the class of effectively simple sets is bounded; but the class of maximal sets is not. Furthermore, the class of computably enumerable sets Turing reducible to a computably enumerable set B is bounded (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Index sets of finite classes of recursively enumerable sets.Louise Hay - 1969 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 34 (1):39-44.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A discrete chain of degrees of index sets.Louise Hay - 1972 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 37 (1):139-149.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Gödel numberings of partial recursive functions.Hartley Rogers - 1958 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 23 (3):331-341.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Belegradek, O., Verbovskiy, V. and Wagner, FO, Coset.J. Y. Halpern, B. M. Kapron, V. S. Harizanov, U. Kohlenbach, P. Oliva, F. Lucas, B. Luttik, P. Matet & M. Pourmahdian - 2003 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 121 (1):287.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Pa Relative to an Enumeration Oracle.G. O. H. Jun Le, Iskander Sh Kalimullin, Joseph S. Miller & Mariya I. Soskova - 2023 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 88 (4):1497-1525.
    Recall that B is PA relative to A if B computes a member of every nonempty $\Pi ^0_1(A)$ class. This two-place relation is invariant under Turing equivalence and so can be thought of as a binary relation on Turing degrees. Miller and Soskova [23] introduced the notion of a $\Pi ^0_1$ class relative to an enumeration oracle A, which they called a $\Pi ^0_1{\left \langle {A}\right \rangle }$ class. We study the induced extension of the relation B is PA relative (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Degrees of unsolvability associated with classes of formalized theories.Solomon Feferman - 1957 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 22 (2):161-175.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Relativizing chaitin's halting probability.Rod Downey, Denis R. Hirschfeldt, Joseph S. Miller & André Nies - 2005 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 5 (02):167-192.
    As a natural example of a 1-random real, Chaitin proposed the halting probability Ω of a universal prefix-free machine. We can relativize this example by considering a universal prefix-free oracle machine U. Let [Formula: see text] be the halting probability of UA; this gives a natural uniform way of producing an A-random real for every A ∈ 2ω. It is this operator which is our primary object of study. We can draw an analogy between the jump operator from computability theory (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Dominical categories: recursion theory without elements.Robert A. di Paola & Alex Heller - 1987 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 52 (3):594-635.
    Dominical categories are categories in which the notions of partial morphisms and their domains become explicit, with the latter being endomorphisms rather than subobjects of their sources. These categories form the basis for a novel abstract formulation of recursion theory, to which the present paper is devoted. The abstractness has of course its usual concomitant advantage of generality: it is interesting to see that many of the fundamental results of recursion theory remain valid in contexts far removed from their classic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations