Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Зеркало Клио: Метафизическое Постижение Истории.Алексей Владиславович Халапсис - 2017 - Днипро, Днепропетровская область, Украина, 49000:
    В монографии представлены несколько смысловых блоков, связанных с восприятием и интерпретацией человеком исторического бытия. Ранние греческие мыслители пытались получить доступ к исходникам (началам) бытия, и эти интенции легли в основу научного знания, а также привели к появлению метафизики. В классической (и в неклассической) метафизике за основу была принята догма Пифагора и Платона о неизменности подлинной реальности, из чего следовало отрицание бытийного характера времени. Автор монографии отказывается от этой догмы и предлагает стратегию обновления метафизики и перехода ее к новому — постнеклассическому (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Mediating Machines.M. Norton Wise - 1988 - Science in Context 2 (1):77-113.
    The ArgumentThe societal context within which science is pursued generally acts as a productive force in the generation of knowledge. To analyze this action it is helpful to consider particular modes of mediation through which societal concerns are projected into the very local and esoteric concerns of a particular domain of research. One such mode of mediation occurs through material systems. Here I treat two such systems – the steam engine and the electric telegraph – in the natural philosophy of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Kant’s Cognitive Semantics, Newton’s Rule Four of Philosophy and Scientific Realism.Kenneth R. Westphal - 2011 - Bulletin of the Hegel Society of Great Britain 63 (1-2):27-49.
    Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason contains an original and powerful semantics of singular cognitive reference which has important implications for epistemology and for philosophy of science. Here I argue that Kant’s semantics directly and strongly supports Newton’s Rule 4 of Philosophy in ways which support Newton’s realism about gravitational force. I begin with Newton’s Rule 4 of Philosophy and its role in Newton’s justification of realism about gravitational force (§2). Next I briefly summarize Kant’s semantics of singular cognitive reference (§3), (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Gretchenfragen an den Naturalisten.Gerhard Vollmer - 2012 - Philosophia Naturalis 49 (2):239-291.
    A philosophical position may be characterized in different ways. Here we try to say how the naturalist answers certain . The questions come from very different areas; the spectrum of subjects is therefore quite mixed. There are, however, aspects of order: We start with (questions about) abstract subjects like logic, mathematics, metaphysics, then turn to problems of realism. And since in general naturalists are realists, the following questions on truth, laws of nature, origin of the universe, cosmology, evolution, body-mind-problem, freedom (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Leonhard Euler’s early lunar theories 1725–1752: Part 2: developing the methods, 1730–1744.Andreas Verdun - 2013 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 67 (5):477-551.
    The analysis of unpublished manuscripts and of the published textbook on mechanics written between about 1730 and 1744 by Euler reveals the invention, application, and establishment of important physical and mathematical principles and procedures. They became central ingredients of an “embryonic” lunar theory that he developed in 1744/1745. The increasing use of equations of motion, although still parametrized by length, became a standard procedure. The principle of the transference of forces was established to set up such equations. Trigonometric series expansions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Leonhard Euler’s early lunar theories 1725–1752: Part 1: first approaches, 1725–1730.Andreas Verdun - 2013 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 67 (3):235-303.
    Leonhard Euler (1707–1783) published two lunar theories in 1753 and 1772. He also published lunar tables in 1745, 1746, and—anonymously—in 1750. There are notebook records, unpublished manuscripts, and manuscript fragments by Euler reflecting the development of his lunar theories between about 1725 until about 1752. These documents might be used to reconstruct Euler’s theory on which he based his calculations of those lunar tables and to analyze the development of his lunar theories within this time span. The results of this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A Very Early Acquaintance with Apollonius of Perga's Treatise on Conic Sections in the Latin West.Sabetai Unguru - 1976 - Centaurus 20 (2):112-128.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Novedad empírica y creación de conceptos.Roberto Torretti - 2016 - Revista de Humanidades de Valparaíso 8:269.
    Debido a la historicidad de la razón, más que inventariar sus principales conceptos en un momento dado nos interesa estudiar el proceso de su formación y fijación. En este artículo se ilustra ese proceso con ejemplos tomados de la historia de la física. El primer ejemplo concierne a la subordinación en el siglo XVII de los fenómenos archiconocidos de la caída libre y el movimiento de los planetas a un concepto nuevo; los restantes, tomados de la electrodinámica del siglo XIX (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • How Percepts and Concepts Engage the Future.Roberto Torretti - 2011 - Foundations of Physics 41 (11):1717-1728.
    With Humean empiricism and its agnostic stance regarding the future as a foil, I take a bird’s eye view of the links between past and future prescribed by ordinary concepts of everyday things and processes, and by scientific models of phenomenal situations. I argue that they entitle us to claim knowledge of the future—including, where appropriate, its necessary course—in a humanly affordable sense of ‘knowledge’.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Getting rid of the Ether. Could Physics have achieved it sooner, with better assistance from Philosophy?Roberto Torretti - 2009 - Theoria 22 (3):353-374.
    The history of the luminiferous ether is sketched with a view to ascertaining what factors may have kept this idea alive until 1905, when Einstein declared it superfluous.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Symplectic Reduction and the Problem of Time in Nonrelativistic Mechanics.Karim P. Y. Thébault - 2012 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 63 (4):789-824.
    Symplectic reduction is a formal process through which degeneracy within the mathematical representations of physical systems displaying gauge symmetry can be controlled via the construction of a reduced phase space. Typically such reduced spaces provide us with a formalism for representing both instantaneous states and evolution uniquely and for this reason can be justifiably afforded the status of fun- damental dynamical arena - the otiose structure having been eliminated from the original phase space. Essential to the application of symplectic reduction (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Ontology of Time and Hyperdynamism.Erwin Tegtmeier - 2009 - Metaphysica 10 (2):185-198.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The anticipation of necessity: Kant on Kepler's laws and universal gravitation.Scott Tanona - 2000 - Philosophy of Science 67 (3):421-443.
    Kant's views on the epistemological status of physical science provide an important example of how a philosophical system can be applied to understand the foundation of scientific theories. Michael Friedman has made considerable progress towards elucidating Kant's philosophy of science; in particular, he has argued that Kant viewed Newton's law of universal gravitation as necessary for the possibility of experiencing what Kant called true motion, which is more than the mere relative motion of appearances but is different from Newton's concept (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The effect of effects on effectiveness: A boon-bane asymmetry.Abigail B. Sussman & Daniel M. Oppenheimer - 2020 - Cognition 199 (C):104240.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The nature of probability.Patrick Suppes - 2010 - Philosophical Studies 147 (1):89 - 102.
    The thesis of this article is that the nature of probability is centered on its formal properties, not on any of its standard interpretations. Section 2 is a survey of Bayesian applications. Section 3 focuses on two examples from physics that seem as completely objective as other physical concepts. Section 4 compares the conflict between subjective Bayesians and objectivists about probability to the earlier strident conflict in physics about the nature of force. Section 5 outlines a pragmatic approach to the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Von der mathematischen zur kritischen Metaphysik der Natur. Lambert und Kant.Gideon Stiening - 2022 - Kantian Journal 41 (2):42-67.
    In the mid-1760s, Johann Heinrich Lambert wrote a letter to Kant who offered cooperation with a view to reforming metaphysics. Based on the short correspondence between the two philosophers, it can be shown that this cooperation could never really come about. Nevertheless the thesis was sometimes put forward in research that Lambert had a defining influence on Kant’s Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science, also, and above all, with regard to the Newton-critical moments of this natur­al theory. However, this thesis can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Huygens on Inertial Structure and Relativity.Marius Stan - 2016 - Philosophy of Science 83 (2):277-298.
    I explain and assess here Huygens’ concept of relative motion. I show that it allows him to ground most of the Law of Inertia, and also to explain rotation. Thereby his concept obviates the need for Newton’s absolute space. Thus his account is a powerful foundation for mechanics, though not without some tension.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Absolute Time: The Limit of Kant's Idealism.Marius Stan - 2019 - Noûs 53 (2):433-461.
    I examine here if Kant can explain our knowledge of duration by showing that time has metric structure. To do so, I spell out two possible solutions: time’s metric could be intrinsic or extrinsic. I argue that Kant’s resources are too weak to secure an intrinsic, transcendentally-based temporal metrics; but he can supply an extrinsic metric, based in a metaphysical fact about matter. I conclude that Transcendental Idealism is incomplete: it cannot account for the durative aspects of experience—or it can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Evolution, teleology and theology.Frans Soontiëns - 1992 - Bijdragen 53 (4):394-406.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Constructivist View of Newton’s Mechanics.H. G. Solari & M. A. Natiello - 2018 - Foundations of Science 24 (2):1-35.
    In the present essay we attempt to reconstruct Newtonian mechanics under the guidance of logical principles and of a constructive approach related to the genetic epistemology of Piaget and García. Instead of addressing Newton’s equations as a set of axioms, ultimately given by the revelation of a prodigious mind, we search for the fundamental knowledge, beliefs and provisional assumptions that can produce classical mechanics. We start by developing our main tool: the no arbitrariness principle, that we present in a form (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • A Constructivist View of Newton’s Mechanics.H. G. Solari & M. A. Natiello - 2019 - Foundations of Science 24 (2):307-341.
    In the present essay we attempt to reconstruct Newtonian mechanics under the guidance of logical principles and of a constructive approach related to the genetic epistemology of Piaget and García (Psychogenesis and the history of science, Columbia University Press, New York, 1989). Instead of addressing Newton’s equations as a set of axioms, ultimately given by the revelation of a prodigious mind, we search for the fundamental knowledge, beliefs and provisional assumptions that can produce classical mechanics. We start by developing our (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Language and other artifacts: socio-cultural dynamics of niche construction.Chris Sinha - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • How complexity originates: Examples from history reveal additional roots to complexity.Peter Schuster - 2016 - Complexity 21 (S2):7-12.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Frege’s philosophy of geometry.Matthias Schirn - 2019 - Synthese 196 (3):929-971.
    In this paper, I critically discuss Frege’s philosophy of geometry with special emphasis on his position in The Foundations of Arithmetic of 1884. In Sect. 2, I argue that that what Frege calls faculty of intuition in his dissertation is probably meant to refer to a capacity of visualizing geometrical configurations structurally in a way which is essentially the same for most Western educated human beings. I further suggest that according to his Habilitationsschrift it is through spatial intuition that we (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Benjamin Robins and the resistance of air.H. M. Barkla - 1973 - Annals of Science 30 (1):107-122.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The nature of time as a puzzle for naturalism.Peter Saulson - 2021 - Zygon 56 (4):922-942.
    Zygon®, Volume 56, Issue 4, Page 922-942, December 2021.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Current Perspectives in Philosophy of Biology.Joaquin Suarez Ruiz & Rodrigo A. Lopez Orellana - 2019 - Humanities Journal of Valparaiso 14:7-426.
    Current Perspectives in Philosophy of Biology.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The snare of simplicity: the Newton–Flamsteed correspondence revisited.J. A. Ruffner - 2013 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 67 (4):415-455.
    The correspondence in 1680 and 1681 between John Flamsteed and Isaac Newton on Flamsteed’s theory of the comet of 1680 tells half the story. Related manuscripts reveal Newton was pursuing his own comprehensive line of inquiry based on principles that were the antithesis of Flamsteed’s procedures. Following generally accepted views in England, Newton’s work was marked by critical evaluation of data but marred by uncritical use of simple calculating techniques based on what might be termed Platonic archetypes of straightness. Flamsteed’s (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The mathematical structure of Newtonian spacetime: Classical dynamics and gravitation. [REVIEW]Waldyr A. Rodrigues, Quintino A. G. de Souza & Yuri Bozhkov - 1995 - Foundations of Physics 25 (6):871-924.
    We give a precise and modern mathematical characterization of the Newtonian spacetime structure (ℕ). Our formulation clarifies the concepts of absolute space, Newton's relative spaces, and absolute time. The concept of reference frames (which are “timelike” vector fields on ℕ) plays a fundamental role in our approach, and the classification of all possible reference frames on ℕ is investigated in detail. We succeed in identifying a Lorentzian structure on ℕ and we study the classical electrodynamics of Maxwell and Lorentz relative (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Anstoß e intersubjetividad en la filosofía temprana de J. G. Fichte.Gustavo Macedo Rodriguez - 2018 - Tópicos: Revista de Filosofía 55:231-250.
    Anstoß e intersubjetividad son dos conceptos fundamentales a partir de los cuales Fichte explica la importancia de la exterioridad en la actividad del yo. En la presente investigación analizo estos dos conceptos centrales en la filosofía temprana de Fichte. Primeramente presento una nueva interpretación del término Anstoß y analizo la relación entre ambos conceptos. Después argumentaré que ambos conceptos forman parte de un proyecto general que consiste en mostrar el carácter holístico de la subjetividad. Se trata, grosso modo, de mostrar (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The intelligibility of the universe.Michael Redhead - 2001 - In Anthony O'Hear (ed.), Philosophy at the New Millennium. pp. 73-90.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • The Intelligibility of the Universe.Michael Redhead - 2001 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 48:73-90.
    Hume famously warned us that the ‘[The] ultimate springs and principles are totally shut up from human curiosity and enquiry’. Or, again, Newton: ‘Hitherto I have not been able to discover the cause of these properties of gravity … and I frame no hypotheses.’ Aristotelian science was concerned with just such questions, the specification of occult qualities, the real essences that answer the question What is matter, etc?, the preoccupation with circular definitions such as dormative virtues, and so on. The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Special theory of relativity in chemistry.Nenad Raos - 2022 - Foundations of Chemistry 24 (1):87-95.
    Application of Einstein special theory of relativity in chemistry seems to be superfluous; energies are too low. The average velocity of electron in hydrogen atom is 1/135 c, making its actual mass only 26,6 ppm bigger than the rest mass. However, for heavier elements relativistic effects have to be taken into account and, more, many phenomena cannot be explained without ascribing new mass to electrons, in accordance with Einstein theory. In this paper such phenomena are described: color of metallic gold (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Quantum mechanics, time, and theology: Indefinite causal order and a new approach to salvation.Emily Qureshi-Hurst & Anna Pearson - 2020 - Zygon 55 (3):663-684.
    Quantum mechanics has recently indicated that, at the fundamental level, temporal order is not fixed. This phenomenon, termed Indefinite Causal Order, is yet to receive metaphysical or theological engagement. We examine Indefinite Causal Order, particularly as it emerges in a 2018 photonic experiment. In this experiment, two operations A and B were shown to be in a superposition with regard to their causal order. Essentially, time, intuitively understood as fixed, flowing, and fundamental, becomes fuzzy. We argue that if Indefinite Causal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Principia’s second law (as Newton understood it) from Galileo to Laplace.Bruce Pourciau - 2020 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 74 (3):183-242.
    Newton certainly regarded his second law of motion in the Principia as a fundamental axiom of mechanics. Yet the works that came after the Principia, the major treatises on the foundations of mechanics in the eighteenth century—by Varignon, Hermann, Euler, Maclaurin, d’Alembert, Euler (again), Lagrange, and Laplace—do not record, cite, discuss, or even mention the Principia’s statement of the second law. Nevertheless, the present study shows that all of these scientists do in fact assume the principle that the Principia’s second (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On the Strangeness of Quantum Mechanics.Marcello Poletti - 2022 - Foundations of Physics 52 (3):1-7.
    The extravagances of quantum mechanics never fail to enrich daily the debate around natural philosophy. Entanglement, non-locality, collapse, many worlds, many minds, and subjectivism have challenged generations of thinkers. Its approach can perhaps be placed in the stream of quantum logic, in which the “strangeness” of QM is “measured” through the violation of Bell’s inequalities and, from there, attempts an interpretative path that preserves realism yet ends up overturning it, restating the fundamental mechanisms of QM as a logical necessity for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kant, Schlick and Friedman on Space, Time and Gravity in Light of Three Lessons from Particle Physics.J. Brian Pitts - 2018 - Erkenntnis 83 (2):135-161.
    Kantian philosophy of space, time and gravity is significantly affected in three ways by particle physics. First, particle physics deflects Schlick’s General Relativity-based critique of synthetic a priori knowledge. Schlick argued that since geometry was not synthetic a priori, nothing was—a key step toward logical empiricism. Particle physics suggests a Kant-friendlier theory of space-time and gravity presumably approximating General Relativity arbitrarily well, massive spin-2 gravity, while retaining a flat space-time geometry that is indirectly observable at large distances. The theory’s roots (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Conceptual Frameworks on the Relationship Between Physics–Mathematics in the Newton Principia Geneva Edition (1822).Raffaele Pisano & Paolo Bussotti - 2022 - Foundations of Science 27 (3).
    The aim of this paper is twofold: (1) to show the principal aspects of the way in which Newton conceived his mathematical concepts and methods and applied them to rational mechanics in his Principia; (2) to explain how the editors of the Geneva Edition interpreted, clarified, and made accessible to a broader public Newton’s perfect but often elliptic proofs. Following this line of inquiry, we will explain the successes of Newton’s mechanics, but also the problematic aspects of his perfect geometrical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Development of the Principle of Virtual Laws and its Conceptual Framework in Mechanics as Fundamental Relationship between Physics and Mathematics.Pisano Raffaele - 2017 - Transversal: International Journal for the Historiography of Science 2:166.
    Generally speaking, virtual displacement or work concerns to a timely idea according to which a motion of a certain body is not the unique possible motion. The process of reducing this motion to a particular magnitude and concept, eventually minimizing as a hypothesis, can be traced back to the Aristotelian school. In the history and philosophy of science one finds various enunciations of the Principle of Virtual Laws and its virtual displacement or work applications, i.e., from Aristotle to Leibniz’s vis (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Genèse de la causalité physique.M. Paty - 2004 - Revue Philosophique De Louvain 102 (3):417-445.
    Les notions ou catégories de causalité et de déterminisme ont accompagné la formation des sciences modernes, et en premier lieu celle de la physique. L'usage courant de nos jours tend souvent, à tort, à les confondre, dans les remises en cause qui en sont faites en physique même. Nous nous proposons, dans ce travail, de clarifier la première de ces notions, plus exactement la causalité physique, en suivant son élaboration avec les débuts de la dynamique, à travers ses premières mises (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Problems between science and theology in the course of their modern history.Wolfhart Pannenberg - 2006 - Zygon 41 (1):105-112.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Breaking the circle: the emergence of Archimedean mechanics in the late Renaissance.Paolo Palmieri - 2008 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 62 (3):301-346.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Will and artifice: the impact of voluntarist theology on early-modern science.Francis Oakley - 2019 - History of European Ideas 45 (6):767-784.
    This article is in part an intervention in the ongoing debate inaugurated by Peter Harrison in 2002 when he called into question the validity of what had come by then to be called ‘the voluntarism and science thesis.’ Though it subsequently drew support from such historians of science as J.E. McGuire, Margaret Osler, Betty Jo Teeter Dobbs and, more recently, John Henry (in rebuttal of Harrison), the origins of the thesis are usually traced back to articles published in 1934–1936 and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Temporalities.Argyris Nicolaidis - 2008 - World Futures 64 (2):109 – 115.
    The notion of time is traced both in Philosophy and in Physics (Newtonian Mechanics, Relativity, Cosmology, Quantum Theory). Distinct temporalities emerge and time appears as the essential condition for the realization of being, in accordance with ideas and theories developed by Peirce, Whitehead, and Heidegger.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Qualities, Properties, and Laws in Newton’s Induction.David Marshall Miller - 2009 - Philosophy of Science 76 (5):1052-1063.
    Newton’s argument for universal gravitation in the Principia eventually rested on the third “Rule of Philosophizing,” which warrants the generalization of “qualities of bodies.” An analysis of the rule and the history of its development indicate that the term ‘quality’ should be taken to include both inherent properties of bodies and relations among systems of bodies, generalized into `laws'. By incorporating law‐induction into the rule, Newton could legitimately rebuff objections to his theory by claiming that universal gravitation was justified by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Framework of space and time from the proto-semiotic perspective.Koichiro Matsuno - 2011 - Biosemiotics 4 (1):103-118.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Transhumanism, Motion, and Human Perfection.Jordan Mason - 2022 - Christian Bioethics 28 (3):185-196.
    Transhumanism’s ideology is marked by a commitment to the “progress” or “perfection” of the human species through technological means. What transhumanists are after is not just therapeutic intervention or optimization of current human capabilities, but an ontological change from human to posthuman. In this article, I critique transhumanist ideology on the grounds that it fundamentally misunderstands human moral perfection as resulting from forces acting upon us (i.e., technological interventions), rather than an internal change of character. This misunderstanding reflects an impoverished (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Kant’s dynamical theory of matter in 1755, and its debt to speculative Newtonian experimentalism.Michela Massimi - 2011 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 42 (4):525-543.
    This paper explores the scientific sources behind Kant’s early dynamic theory of matter in 1755, with a focus on two main Kant’s writings: Universal Natural History and Theory of the Heavens and On Fire. The year 1755 has often been portrayed by Kantian scholars as a turning point in the intellectual career of the young Kant, with his much debated conversion to Newton. Via a careful analysis of some salient themes in the two aforementioned works, and a reconstruction of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Cartesian echoes in Kant’s philosophy of nature.Michela Massimi & Silvia De Bianchi - 2013 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 44 (3):481-492.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The (un)detectability of absolute Newtonian masses.Niels C. M. Martens - 2019 - Synthese 198 (3):2511-2550.
    Absolutism about mass claims that mass ratios obtain in virtue of absolute masses. Comparativism denies this. Dasgupta, Oxford studies in metaphysics, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2013) argues for comparativism about mass, in the context of Newtonian Gravity. Such an argument requires proving that comparativism is empirically adequate. Dasgupta equates this to showing that absolute masses are undetectable, and attempts to do so. This paper develops an argument by Baker to the contrary: absolute masses are in fact empirically meaningful, that is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations