Switch to: References

Citations of:

Semantics and necessary truth

New Haven,: Yale University Press (1958)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. (1 other version)Critical notice. [REVIEW]John V. Canfield - 1981 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 11 (2):333-356.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (2 other versions)What Computations (Still, Still) Can't Do: Jerry Fodor on Computation and Modularity.Robert A. Wilson - 2004 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 34 (sup1):407-425.
    Fodor's thinking on modularity has been influential throughout a range of the areas studying cognition, chiefly as a prod for positive work on modularity and domain-specificity. In _The Mind Doesn't Work That Way_, Fodor has developed the dark message of _The Modularity of Mind_ regarding the limits to modularity and computational analyses. This paper offers a critical assessment of Fodor's scepticism with an eye to highlighting some broader issues in play, including the nature of computation and the role of recent (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Normativity and Mathematics: A Wittgensteinian Approach to the Study of Number.J. Robert Loftis - 1999 - Dissertation, Northwestern University
    I argue for the Wittgensteinian thesis that mathematical statements are expressions of norms, rather than descriptions of the world. An expression of a norm is a statement like a promise or a New Year's resolution, which says that someone is committed or entitled to a certain line of action. A expression of a norm is not a mere description of a regularity of human behavior, nor is it merely a descriptive statement which happens to entail a norms. The view can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Same but Different.Anna-Sofia Maurin - 2005 - Metaphysica 6 (1):131-146.
    Paper responding to critique of Maurin (2002) presented by Herbert Hochberg in his “Relations, Properties and Particulars” (2004).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • The Myth of Logical Behaviourism and the Origins of the Identity Theory.Sean Crawford - 2013 - In Michael Beaney (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of The History of Analytic Philosophy. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
    The identity theory’s rise to prominence in analytic philosophy of mind during the late 1950s and early 1960s is widely seen as a watershed in the development of physicalism, in the sense that whereas logical behaviourism proposed analytic and a priori ascertainable identities between the meanings of mental and physical-behavioural concepts, the identity theory proposed synthetic and a posteriori knowable identities between mental and physical properties. While this watershed does exist, the standard account of it is misleading, as it is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Quine on logical truth.Dilip Kumar Basu - 1971 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 9 (4):341-343.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reductive theories of modality.Theodore Sider - 2003 - In Michael J. Loux & Dean W. Zimmerman (eds.), The Oxford handbook of metaphysics. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 180-208.
    Logic begins but does not end with the study of truth and falsity. Within truth there are the modes of truth, ways of being true: necessary truth and contingent truth. When a proposition is true, we may ask whether it could have been false. If so, then it is contingently true. If not, then it is necessarily true; it must be true; it could not have been false. Falsity has modes as well: a false proposition that could not have been (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   91 citations  
  • Kant’s Conception of Analytic Judgment.Ian Proops - 2005 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 70 (3):588–612.
    In the 'Critique of Pure Reason' Kant appears to characterize analytic judgments in four distinct ways: once in terms of “containment,” a second time in terms of “identity,” a third time in terms of the explicative–ampliative contrast, and a fourth time in terms of the notion of “cognizability in accordance with the principle of contradiction.” The paper asks: Which of these characterizations—or apparent characterizations—best captures Kant’s conception of analyticity in the first Critique? It suggests: “the second.” It argues, further, that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Logical Conventionalism.Jared Warren - unknown - In Filippo Ferrari, Elke Brendel, Massimiliano Carrara, Ole Hjortland, Gil Sagi, Gila Sher & Florian Steinberger (eds.), Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Logic. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
    Once upon a time, logical conventionalism was the most popular philosophical theory of logic. It was heavily favored by empiricists, logical positivists, and naturalists. According to logical conventionalism, linguistic conventions explain logical truth, validity, and modality. And conventions themselves are merely syntactic rules of language use, including inference rules. Logical conventionalism promised to eliminate mystery from the philosophy of logic by showing that both the metaphysics and epistemology of logic fit into a scientific picture of reality. For naturalists of all (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Two Kindred Neo-Kantian Philosophies of Science: Pap’s The A Priori in Physical Theory and Cassirer’s Determinism and Indeterminism in Modern Physics.Thomas Mormann - 2021 - Journal of Transcendental Philosophy 1 (1).
    The main thesis of this paper is that Pap’s The Functional A Priori of Physical Theory (Pap 1946, henceforth FAP) and Cassirer’s Determinism and Indeterminism in Modern Physics (Cassirer 1937, henceforth DI) may be conceived as two kindred accounts of a late Neo-Kantian philosophy of science. They elucidate and clarify each other mutually by elaborating conceptual possibilities and pointing out affinities of neo-Kantian ideas with other currents of 20th century’s philosophy of science, namely, pragmatism, conventionalism, and logical empiricism. Taking into (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On the concept of material consequence.Tomis Kapitan - 1982 - History and Philosophy of Logic 3 (2):193-211.
    Everyday reasoning is replete with arguments which, though not logically valid, nonetheless harbor a measure of credibility in their own right. Here the claim that such arguments force us to acknowledge material validity, in addition to logical validity, is advanced, and criteria that attempt to unpack this concept are examined in detail. Of special concern is the effort to model these criteria on explications of logical validity that rely on notions of substitutivity and logical form. It is argued, however, that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Conventionalism and the contingency of conventions.Alan Sidelle - 2009 - Noûs 43 (2):224-241.
    One common objection to Conventionalism about modality is that since it is contingent what our conventions are, the modal facts themselves will thereby be contingent. A standard reply is that Conventionalists can accept this, if they reject the S4 axiom, that what is possibly possible is possible. I first argue that this reply is inadequate, but then continue to argue that it is not needed, because the Conventionalist need not concede that the contingency of our conventions has any bearing on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Hume and human error.Mark Hooper - unknown
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How Does the Laboratory of the Mind Work?Nebojsa Kujundzic - 1993 - Dialogue 32 (3):573-.
    The Laboratory of the Mindwas written with two purposes in mind. The first was to contribute to the growing literature on thought experiments with a selection of the most interesting examples of the genre. The second and much more ambitious purpose was to serve as a “first attempt at a rationalist interpretation of science”.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Scepticism and Contrast.Rolf A. George - 1971 - Dialogue 10 (1):92-95.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The laws of logic.E. D. Klemke - 1966 - Philosophy of Science 33 (3):271-277.
    In Reason and Analysis, Prof. Brand Blanshard criticises the logical empiricist view regarding necessary statements, including the laws of logic. He distinguishes four component these of this view: (I) Necessary statements--here, the laws of logic--are resolutions or reports of linguistic usage. (II) They are conventions. (III) They are analytic (tautologies). (IV) They say nothing about the world. In this paper I first show that Prof. Blanshard is essentially right in his criticisms of (I), (II), and (IV); but that he has (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Particulars, substrata, and the identity of indiscernibles.Albert Casullo - 1982 - Philosophy of Science 49 (4):591-603.
    This paper examines the view that ordinary particulars are complexes of universals. Russell's attempt to develop such a theory is articulated and defended against some common misinterpretations and unfounded criticisms in Section I. The next two sections address an argument which is standardly cited as the primary problem confronting the theory: (1) it is committed to the necessary truth of the principle of the identity of indiscernibles; (2) the principle is not necessarily true. It is argued in Section II that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Alleged problems in attributing beliefs, and intentionality, to animals.Richard Routley - 1981 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 24 (4):385-417.
    The ordinary attribution of intentionality to (nonhuman) animals raises serious problems for fashionable linguistic accounts of belief and of intentionality generally; and many of the alleged problems arise from such linguistic theories of mind. Another deeper source of alleged problems is the apartness thesis, that there is a significant difference in kind, with substantial moral import, between humans and other animals; for the last lines of defence of this erroneous thesis consist in making out that there are significant intentional differences. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Return of the A Priori.Philip Hanson & Bruce Hunter - 1992 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 22 (sup1):1-51.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (1 other version)Critical notice.Bernard Linsky - 1984 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 14 (3):499-515.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Logical Truth.Mario Gomez-Torrente - 2014 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Frege and the determination of reference.Gilead Bar-Elli - 1981 - Erkenntnis 16 (1):137 - 160.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Sentence-relativity and the necessary a posteriori.Kai-Yee Wong - 1996 - Philosophical Studies 83 (1):53 - 91.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Analyticity and the A Priori.Albert Casullo - 1992 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 18 (sup1):113-150.
    The analytic/synthetic distinction has played a central role in discussions of a priori knowledge throughout the twentieth century. One of the primary reasons for the prominence of this distinction is the widespread influence of the tradition of logical empiricism which endorsed the following principles: All analytic propositions are knowable a prioriand All propositions knowable a priori are analytic.Hence, proponents of the a priori often argue in support of the contention that the propositions of a particular discipline, say mathematics or logic, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Reason and refutation: a review of two recent books by Harvey Siegel. [REVIEW]Mark Weinstein - 1992 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 11 (3):231-263.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)Wittgenstein's Lectures on the Foundations of Mathematics, Cambridge, 1939. [REVIEW]John V. Canfield - 1981 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 11 (2):333-356.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Analyticity, Undeniability, and Truth.James van Cleve - 1992 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 22 (sup1):89-111.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The inexplicability of identity.Stewart Candlish - 1971 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 49 (1):23 – 37.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Review Essay: The `Two Dogmas of Empiricism' 50 Years On.Paolo Parrini - 2007 - Diogenes 54 (4):91-101.
    ...its identity in the pragmatics of elucidation, and not in some sort of special knowledge...yer's essay (`Implicit Thoughts: Quine, Frege and Kant on Analytic Propositions...by Quine, and attributed to Kant, Frege and Carnap, has nothing in common..
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Three Basic Ontological Relations Concerning The Physical Realm.David GrÜnberg - 2005 - Metaphysica 6 (1):85-109.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Reference and Essence. [REVIEW]Bernard Linsky - 1984 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 14 (3):499-515.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark