- Why we view the brain as a computer.Oron Shagrir - 2006 - Synthese 153 (3):393-416.details
|
|
In defence of narrow mindedness.Frances Egan - 1999 - Mind and Language 14 (2):177-94.details
|
|
Chomsky and Egan on computational theories of vision.Arnold Silverberg - 2006 - Minds and Machines 16 (4):495-524.details
|
|
Why be an anti-individualist?Laura Schroeter - 2008 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 77 (1):105-141.details
|
|
(1 other version)The language of thought hypothesis.Murat Aydede - 2010 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.details
|
|
Constructing persons: On the personal–subpersonal distinction.Mason Westfall - 2024 - Philosophical Psychology 37 (4):831-860.details
|
|
Updating the Frame Problem for Artificial Intelligence Research.Lisa Miracchi - 2020 - Journal of Artificial Intelligence and Consciousness 7 (2):217-230.details
|
|
Language and scientific explanation: Where does semantics fit in?Eran Asoulin - 2020 - Berlin, Germany: Language Science Press.details
|
|
The content of Marr’s information-processing framework.J. Brendan Ritchie - 2019 - Philosophical Psychology 32 (7):1078-1099.details
|
|
A Theory of Practical Meaning.Carlotta Pavese - 2017 - Philosophical Topics 45 (2):65-96.details
|
|
Against Structuralist Theories of Computational Implementation.Michael Rescorla - 2013 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 64 (4):681-707.details
|
|
(1 other version)The philosophy of computer science.Raymond Turner - 2013 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.details
|
|
Semantic externalism and the mechanics of thought.Carrie Figdor - 2009 - Minds and Machines 19 (1):1-24.details
|
|
Computation without representation.Gualtiero Piccinini - 2008 - Philosophical Studies 137 (2):205-241.details
|
|
Content, illusion, partition.York H. Gunther - 2001 - Philosophical Studies 102 (2):185-202.details
|
|
A competence framework for artificial intelligence research.Lisa Miracchi - 2019 - Philosophical Psychology 32 (5):588-633.details
|
|
The Causal Relevance of Content to Computation.Michael Rescorla - 2012 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 88 (1):173-208.details
|
|
Nonconceptual Content: From Perceptual Experience to Subpersonal Computational States.José Luis Bermúdez - 1995 - Mind and Language 10 (4):333-369.details
|
|
The Commitment to LOT.Víctor M. Verdejo - 2016 - Dialogue 55 (2):313-341.details
|
|
Situated action, symbol systems and universal computation.Andrew Wells - 1996 - Minds and Machines 6 (1):33-46.details
|
|
Are Computational Transitions Sensitive to Semantics?Michael Rescorla - 2012 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 90 (4):703-721.details
|
|
(1 other version)1. Marr on Computational-Level Theories Marr on Computational-Level Theories (pp. 477-500).Oron Shagrir, John D. Norton, Holger Andreas, Jouni-Matti Kuukkanen, Aris Spanos, Eckhart Arnold, Elliott Sober, Peter Gildenhuys & Adela Helena Roszkowski - 2010 - Philosophy of Science 77 (4):477-500.details
|
|
Posséder un concept selon Peacocke.Martin Montminy - 2001 - Dialogue 40 (2):219-.details
|
|
The semantic view of computation and the argument from the cognitive science practice.Alfredo Paternoster & Fabrizio Calzavarini - 2022 - Synthese 200 (2):1-24.details
|
|
The scope and limits of Chomsky's naturalism.Pierre Jacob - unknowndetails
|
|