Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The structuralist view of economic theories: A review essay: The case of general equilibrium in particular.D. Wade Hands - 1985 - Economics and Philosophy 1 (2):303-.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Incommensurability, Comparability, and Non-reductive Ontological Relations.José L. Falguera & Xavier Donato-Rodríguez - 2016 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 47 (1):37-58.
    We begin by highlighting some points related to Kuhn’s later thoughts on the incommensurability thesis and then show to what extent the standard version of the thesis given by the structuralist metatheory allows us to capture Kuhn’s ideas. Our main aim is to establish what constitutes the basis of comparability between incommensurable theories, even in cases of incommensurability with respect to theoretical and non-theoretical terms. We propose that comparability between incommensurable theories requires some connection between their respective ontologies that can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The development of structuralism. [REVIEW]Werner Diederich - 1989 - Erkenntnis 30 (3):363 - 386.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Integrated HPS? Formal versus historical approaches to philosophy of science.Bobby Vos - 2021 - Synthese 199 (5-6):14509-14533.
    The project of integrated HPS has occupied philosophers of science in one form or another since at least the 1960s. Yet, despite this substantial interest in bringing together philosophical and historical reflections on the nature of science, history of science and formal philosophy of science remain as divided as ever. In this paper, I will argue that the continuing separation between historical and formal philosophy of science is ill-founded. I will argue for this in both abstract and concrete terms. At (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Incommensurability and reduction reconsidered.David Pearce - 1986 - Erkenntnis 24 (3):293 - 308.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • On reduction of theories.Andreas Kamlah - 1985 - Erkenntnis 22 (1-3):119 - 142.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Reduction, representation and commensurability of theories.Peter Schroeder-Heister & Frank Schaefer - 1989 - Philosophy of Science 56 (1):130-157.
    Theories in the usual sense, as characterized by a language and a set of theorems in that language ("statement view"), are related to theories in the structuralist sense, in turn characterized by a set of potential models and a subset thereof as models ("non-statement view", J. Sneed, W. Stegmüller). It is shown that reductions of theories in the structuralist sense (that is, functions on structures) give rise to so-called "representations" of theories in the statement sense and vice versa, where representations (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Translation, reduction and commensurability: A note on Schroeder-heister and Schaefer.David Pearce - 1989 - Philosophy of Science 56 (1):158-164.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Research traditions, incommensurability and scientific progress.David Pearce - 1984 - Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 15 (2):261-271.
    Summary In hisProgress and its Problems, Laudan dismisses the problem of incommensurability in science by endorsing two general assertions. The first claims there are actually no incommensurable pairs of theories or research traditions; the second maintains that his problem-solving model of scientific progress would be able rationally to appraise even incommensurable pairs of theories or traditions (are compare them for their progressiveness). I argue here that Laudan fails to provide a plausible defence of either thesis, and that this creates some (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Approximative explanation is deductive-nomological.David Pearce & Veikko Rantala - 1985 - Philosophy of Science 52 (1):126-140.
    We revive the idea that a deductive-nomological explanation of a scientific theory by its successor may be defensible, even in those common and troublesome cases where the theories concerned are mutually incompatible; and limiting, approximating and counterfactual assumptions may be required in order to define a logical relation between them. Our solution is based on a general characterization of limiting relations between physical theories using the method of nonstandard analysis.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Incommensurability, reduction, and translation.W. Balzer - 1985 - Erkenntnis 23 (3):255 - 267.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Completeness for systems including real numbers.W. Balzer & M. Reiter - 1989 - Studia Logica 48 (1):67 - 75.
    The usual completeness theorem for first-order logic is extended in order to allow for a natural incorporation of real analysis. Essentially, this is achieved by building in the set of real numbers into the structures for the language, and by adjusting other semantical notions accordingly. We use many-sorted languages so that the resulting formal systems are general enough for axiomatic treatments of empirical theories without recourse to elements of set theory which are difficult to interprete empirically. Thus we provide a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations