Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Reconciling Divisions in the Field of Authentic Education.Ariel Sarid - 2015 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 49 (3):473-489.
    The aim of this article is twofold: first, to identify and address three central divisions in the field of authentic education that introduce ambiguity and at times inconsistencies within the field of authentic education. These divisions concern a) the relationship between autonomy and authenticity; b) the division between the two basic attitudes towards ‘care’ in the authenticity literature, and; c) the well-worn division between objective and subjective realms of knowledge and identity construction. Addressing these divisions through Charles Taylor's distinction between (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)Vision and Elusiveness in Philosophy of Education: R. S. Peters on the Legacy of Michael Oakeshott.Kevin Williams - 2009 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 43 (supplement s1):223-240.
    Despite his elusiveness on important issues, there is much in Michael Oakeshott's educational vision that Richard Peters quite rightly wishes to endorse. The main aim of this essay is, however, to consider Peters' justifiable critique of three features of Oakeshott's work. These are (1) the rigidity of his distinction between vocational and university education, (2) the lack of clarity and accuracy in his philosophy of teaching and learning, especially the under-conceptualisation of the role of example in teaching, (3) the over-emphasis (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • (1 other version)Richard Peters and Valuing Authenticity.M. A. B. Degenhardt - 2009 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 43 (supplement s1):209-222.
    Richard Peters has been praised for the authenticity of his philosophy, and inquiry into aspects of the development of his philosophy reveals a profound authenticity. Yet authenticity is something he seems not to favour. The apparent paradox is resolved by observing historical changes in the understanding of authenticity as an important value. Possibilities are noted for further explorations as to how to understand and value it as an educational ideal.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Educational theory and the conceptual framework of common sense.J. D. Marshall - 1977 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 9 (1):17–31.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The teaching of controversial issues.D. W. Dewhurst - 1992 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 26 (2):153–163.
    ABSTRACT The article criticizes certain subjectivist and isolationist stances on controversial issues, and construes the teaching of controversial issues as an interpersonal task. On this view the teacher (1) encourages students to enter into the perspectives of others; (2) establishes points of contact which make reasoned discourse possible; and (3) inducts students into a wider domain where they are provided with knowledge about controversies as well as the skills for handling those controversies. All of this requires considerable intervention on the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Is there any relationship between educational theory and practice?Beverley Shaw - 1981 - British Journal of Educational Studies 29 (1):19-28.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Respect.Robin S. Dillon - 2018 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • Emptiness and the Education of the Emotions.Jeffrey Morgan - 2015 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 47 (3):291-304.
    This article argues that Buddhist philosophy offers a plausible theory of the education of the emotions. Emotions are analyzed as cognitive feeling events in which the subject is passive. The education of the emotions is possible if and only if it is possible to evaluate one’s emotional life (the normative condition) and it is possible to satisfy the normative condition through learning (the pedagogical condition). Drawing on the Four Noble Truths of Buddhism, as well as the concepts of conditioned arising, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • R. S. Peters and J. H. Newman on the Aims of Education.Jānis Ozoliņš - 2013 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 45 (2):153-170.
    R. S. Peters never explicitly talks about wisdom as being an aim of education. He does, however, in numerous places, emphasize that education is of the whole person and that, whatever else it might be about, it involves the development of knowledge and understanding. Being educated, he claims, is incompatible with being narrowly specialized. Moreover, he argues, education enables a person to have a different perspective on things, ‘to travel with a different view’ [Peters, R. S. (1967). What is an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Richard Peters's theory of moral development.Bernadette M. Tobin - 1989 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 23 (1):15–27.
    Bernadette M Tobin; Richard Peters's Theory of Moral Development, Journal of Philosophy of Education, Volume 23, Issue 1, 30 May 2006, Pages 15–27, https://doi.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)Autonomy in R. S. Peters' Educational Theory.Stefaan E. Cuypers - 2009 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 43 (supplement s1):189-207.
    Autonomy is, among other things, an actual psychological condition, a capacity that can be developed, and an educational ideal. This paper contextualises, analyses, criticises and extends the theory of Richard S. Peters on these three aspects of autonomy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Education and the promotion of human freedom.David Carr - 1982 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 14 (1):37–49.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Reason and Virtues: The Paradox of R. S. Peters on Moral Education.Graham Haydon - 2009 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 43 (supplement s1):173-188.
    This article examines the work of R. S. Peters on moral development and moral education, as represented in his papers collected under that name, pointing out that these writings have been relatively neglected. It approaches these writings through the lens of the ‘familiar story’ that philosophical work on this topic switched during, roughly, the 1980s from an emphasis on rational principles to an emphasis on virtues and care. Starting from what Peters called ‘the paradox of moral education’—roughly, that a rational (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Discourses of the reflective educator.Paddy Walsh - 1992 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 26 (2):139–151.
    ABSTRACT The current paradigm of educational theory as‘emergent in practice’ might sooner have provoked, and here does provoke, an analysis of the distinctive profile of educational practice. This practice is shown to be (inter alia) ‘philosophical’ by virtue of its integral quest for a coherent view of life. A theory that is adequate to this practice will be a‘cluster’ of four interconnected ‘discourses’ (each already in use within mature practice itselfl, not only deliberative and evaluative discourses but also utopian and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Indoctrination, intellectual virtues and rational emotions.Ben Spiecker - 1987 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 21 (2):261–266.
    Ben Spiecker; Indoctrination, Intellectual Virtues and Rational Emotions, Journal of Philosophy of Education, Volume 21, Issue 2, 30 May 2006, Pages 261–266, ht.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A sense of identity: Prolegomena to a social theory of personal identity.John D. GreenwooD - 1994 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 24 (1):25–46.
    A philosophical account of personal identity - in terms of the maintenance of fundamental beliefs, principles and commitments by spatiotemporally continuous particulars - is sketched, an account which is able to incorporate a social and relational conception of personal identity, and thus serve as the basis for a social psychological theory of personal identity - in terms of the pursuit of identity projects’within social collectives. Some implications of this theory are developed, concerning the relation between identity and individualism, responsibility and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reflections on Peters' View of the Nature and Purpose of Work in Philosophy of Education.D. N. Aspin - 2013 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 45 (2):219-235.
    In this article I describe the analytic approach adopted by Peters, his colleagues and followers of the ?London line? in the 1960s and 1970s and argue that, even in those times, other approaches to philosophy of education were being valued and practised. I show that Peters and his colleagues later became aware of the need for philosophy of education to become aware of and take in hand a new set of agendas and address the list of substantive issues inherent in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Respectability and Relevance: Reflections on Richard Peters and analytic philosophy of education.Ivan Snook - 2013 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 45 (2):191-201.
    I argue that, after Dewey, Peters was the first modern philosopher of education to write material (in English) that was both philosophically respectable and relevant to the day-to-day concerns of teachers. Since then, some philosophers of education have remained (more or less) relevant but not really respectable while others have ?taken off into the skies? learning acclaim from the philosophical community but ceasing to produce anything which would be of any relevance to teachers in their work. I suggest that Peters (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Liberal Education and the Teleological Question; or Why Should a Dentist Read Chaucer?Kenneth B. Mcintyre - 2012 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 46 (4):341-363.
    This essay consists of an examination of the work of three thinkers who conceive of liberal education primarily in teleological terms, and, implicitly if not explicitly, attempt to offer some answer to the question: what does it mean to be fully human? John Henry Newman, T. S. Eliot, and Josef Pieper developed their understanding of liberal education from their own intellectual and religious experience, which was informed by a specifically Christian conception of the place of education in a fully developed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Learning Our Concepts.Megan J. Laverty - 2009 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 43 (supplement s1):27-40.
    Richard Stanley Peters appreciates the centrality of concepts for everyday life, however, he fails to recognize their pedagogical dimension. He distinguishes concepts employed at the first-order (our ordinary language-use) from second-order conceptual clarification (conducted exclusively by academically trained philosophers). This distinction serves to elevate the discipline of philosophy at the expense of our ordinary language-use. I revisit this distinction and argue that our first-order use of concepts encompasses second-order concern. Individuals learn and teach concepts as they use them. Conceptual understanding (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Piaget's theory and its value for teachers.S. C. Clark - 1995 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 27 (2):64–88.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Learning to live with emotion.Jeffrey Morgan - 1994 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 26 (2):67–81.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Experience and expression: The moral linguistic constitution of emotions.George Turski - 1991 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 21 (4):373–392.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation