Switch to: References

Citations of:

L'espace et le temps

Scientia 6 (12):159 (1912)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Interpreting Heisenberg interpreting quantum states.Simon Friederich - 2012 - Philosophia Naturalis 50 (1):85-114.
    The paper investigates possible readings of the later Heisenberg's remarks on the nature of quantum states. It discusses, in particular, whether Heisenberg should be seen as a proponent of the epistemic conception of states – the view that quantum states are not descriptions of quantum systems but rather reflect the state assigning observers' epistemic relations to these systems. On the one hand, it seems plausible that Heisenberg subscribes to that view, given how he defends the notorious "collapse of the wave (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • “The soul of the fact”—Poincaréand proof.Jeremy Gray - 2014 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 47 (C):142-150.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Henri Poincaré's philosophy of science.David Stump - 1989 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 20 (3):335-363.
    Poincare’s arguments for his thesis of the conventionality of metric depend on a relationalist program for dynamics, not on any general philosophical interpretation of science. I will sketch Poincare’s development of the relationalist program and show that his arguments for the conventionality of metric do not depend on any global strategies such as a general empiricism or Duhemian underdetermination arguments. Poincare’s theory of space, while empirically false, is more philosophically sophisticated than his critics have claimed.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Henri Poincaré et l’espace-temps conventionnel.Scott Walter - 2008 - Cahiers de Philosophie de L’Université de Caen 45:87-119.
    According to the conventionalist doctrine of space elaborated by the French philosopher-scientist Henri Poincaré in the 1890s, the geometry of physical space is a matter of definition, not of fact. Poincaré’s Hertz-inspired view of the role of hypothesis in science guided his interpretation of the theory of relativity (1905), which he found to be in violation of the axiom of free mobility of invariable solids. In a quixotic effort to save the Euclidean geometry that relied on this axiom, Poincaré extended (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Poincaré on clocks in motion.Scott A. Walter - 2014 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 47:131-141.
    Recently-discovered manuscripts throw new light on Poincaré’s discovery of the Lorentz group, and his ether-based interpretation of the Lorentz transformation. At first, Poincaré postulated longitudinal contraction of bodies in motion with respect to the ether, and ignored time deformation. In April, 1909, he acknowledged temporal deformation due to translation, obtaining thereby a theory of relativity more compatible with those of Einstein and Minkowski.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Introdução a três textos de Einstein sobre a geometria, a teoria física e a experiência.Michel Paty - 2005 - Scientiae Studia 3 (4):641-662.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark