Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. State control: Changing tools and language.M. Steriade - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):421-423.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Avoid the push-pull dilemma in explanation.Kenneth M. Steele - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (2):233-234.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Popper, laws, and the exclusion of biology from genuine science.David N. Stamos - 2007 - Acta Biotheoretica 55 (4):357-375.
    The primary purpose of this paper is to argue that biologists should stop citing Karl Popper on what a genuinely scientific theory is. Various ways in which biologists cite Popper on this matter are surveyed, including the use of Popper to settle debates on methodology in phylogenetic systematics. It is then argued that the received view on Popper—namely, that a genuinely scientific theory is an empirically falsifiable one—is seriously mistaken, that Popper’s real view was that genuinely scientific theories have the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • In the beginning was the word.J. E. R. Staddon - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):390-391.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Testing a precise null hypothesis: the case of Lindley’s paradox.Jan Sprenger - 2013 - Philosophy of Science 80 (5):733-744.
    The interpretation of tests of a point null hypothesis against an unspecified alternative is a classical and yet unresolved issue in statistical methodology. This paper approaches the problem from the perspective of Lindley's Paradox: the divergence of Bayesian and frequentist inference in hypothesis tests with large sample size. I contend that the standard approaches in both frameworks fail to resolve the paradox. As an alternative, I suggest the Bayesian Reference Criterion: it targets the predictive performance of the null hypothesis in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Are free associations necessarily contaminated?Donald P. Spence - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):259-259.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Behavior, theories, and the inner.Ernest Sosa - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):537-539.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kuhn's alternative path: Science and the social resistance to criticism.Stephanie Solomon - 2010 - Perspectives on Science 18 (3):352-368.
    Popper: I do admit that at any moment we are prisoners caught in the framework of our theories; our expectations; our past experiences; our language. But we are prisoners in a Pickwickian sense: if we try, we can break out of our framework at any time. Admittedly, we shall find ourselves again in a framework, but it will be a better and roomier one; and we can at any moment break out of it again.Kuhn: If that possibility were routinely available, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Extremum descriptions, process laws and minimality heuristics.Elliott Sober - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (2):232-233.
    The examples and concepts that Shoemaker cites are rather heterogeneous. Some distinctions need to be drawn. An optimality thesis involves not just an ordering of options, but a value judgment about them. So let us begin by distinguishing minimality from optimality. And the concept of minimality can play a variety of roles, among which I distinguish between extremum descriptions, statements hypothesizing an optimizing process, and methodological recommendations. Finally, I consider how the three categories relate to Shoemaker’s question that “Who is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is sociopathy a type or not? Will the “real” sociopathy please stand up?James Snyder - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (3):575-576.
    The validity of the classification of “primary sociopaths” as a qualitatively distinct group in the general population is questioned. Cenetic variation in the experience and expression of emotions may play a role in the development of antisocial behavior. However, research clearly documents that socialization environments powerfully modify the expression of genetic biases in a manner that increases or decreases the risk for “sociopathy.”.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Some comments on the inability of sociology of science to explain science.Steven Miller & Marcel Fredericks - 1994 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 20 (1-2):73-86.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Modal knowledge and transmodularity.Leslie Smith - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):729-730.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Theoretical contingencies.B. F. Skinner - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):541-546.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Methods and theories in the experimental analysis of behavior.B. F. Skinner - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):511-523.
    We owe most scientific knowledge to methods of inquiry that are never formally analyzed. The analysis of behavior does not call for hypothetico-deductive methods. Statistics, taught in lieu of scientific method, is incompatible with major features of much laboratory research. Squeezing significance out of ambiguous data discourages the more promising step of scrapping the experiment and starting again. As a consequence, psychologists have taken flight from the laboratory. They have fled to Real People and the human interest of “real life,” (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Why Experimentum Crucis is Possible in Psychology of Perception.Michele Sinico - 2018 - Gestalt Theory 40 (1):45-57.
    Summary This paper examines the experimentum crucis under the light of the Duhem’s holistic thesis. This methodological instrument is not usable in physics, because physical theories are always logically connected to many assumptions. On the contrary, it is usable in psychological research oriented to perceptual laws, when these laws are, without any hypothetical term, isolated systems. An application of experimentum crucis in Experimental Phenomenology of perception is presented. In conclusion, the role of perceptual knowledge as an essential assumption in other (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Review of Eemeren & Garssen (2008): Controversy and Confrontation: Relating Controversy Analysis with Argumentation Theory. [REVIEW]Inês Signorini - 2010 - Pragmatics and Cognition 18 (1):181-187.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Location of the systems generating REM sleep: Lateral versus medial pons.Jerome M. Siegel & Dennis J. McGinty - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):420-421.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The challenge of representational redescription.Thomas R. Shultz - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):728-729.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Underlabourers for science or toolmakers for society? [REVIEW]John Shotter - 1990 - History of the Human Sciences 3 (3):443-457.
    Roy Bhaskar, Reclaiming Reality: a Critical Introduction to Contemporary Philosophy, London: Verso, 1989, £24.95, paper £8.95, ix + 218 pp.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The question: Not shall_ it be, but _which shall it be?Charles P. Shimp - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):536-537.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • The REM generator: Here, there, and everywhere?Priyattam J. Shiromani & J. Christian Gillin - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):419-420.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Historicism, behaviorism, and the conceptual status of memory representations in animals.Charles P. Shimp - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):389-390.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Popper, Objectification, and the Problem of the Public Sphere.Jeremy Shearmur - 2016 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 46 (4):392-411.
    Shearmur argues for the importance of Popper’s ideas about World 3, and against the idea that they should be re-interpreted in social terms. However, he also argues for the importance of Popper’s ideas about methodological rules—and that these may be given a partially social interpretation. The content of our ideas may in consequence differ from what we take it to be, as a consequence of our institutions and practices operating as methodological rules. He also explores related ideas about the interplay (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Popper, political philosophy, and social democracy: Reply to Eidlin.Jeremy Shearmur - 2006 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 18 (4):361-376.
    The later thought of Karl Popper—notably, his ideas about traditions and his “modified essentialism” in the philosophy of natural science— should lead to revisions in the political philosophy set out in The Open Society and Its Enemies. The structural approach allowed for by Popper's modified essentialism, and the delicate nature of traditions, buttress certain issues raised by Friedrich Hayek that pose serious problems for Popper's social‐democratic approach to politics. Fred Eidlin's review essay on my Political Thought of Karl Popper misses (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Expectancy: The endogenous source of anticipatory activities, including “pseudoconditioned” responses.Patrick J. Sheafor - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):387-389.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • An argument for the evidential standing of psychoanalytic data.Howard Shevrin - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):257-259.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Rational agents, real people and the quest for optimality.Eldar Shafir - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (2):232-232.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Towards a theory of openness to criticism.Tom Settle, I. C. Jarvie & Joseph Agassi - 1974 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 4 (1):83-90.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The point of positive evidence—reply to professor Feyerabend.T. W. Settle - 1969 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 20 (4):352-355.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Deutscher's problem is not Popper's problem.T. W. Settle - 1969 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 47 (2):216 – 219.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Knowledge Argument Against Materialism and the Strategy of Phenomenal Concepts.Dmytro Sepetyi - 2023 - Filosofska Dumka (Philosophical Thought) 3:93-110.
    Materialism/physicalism that generally dominates in the contemporary analytic philosophy is challenged by fairly powerful anti-materialist arguments, notably the zombie argument (most influentially defended by David Chalmers) and the knowledge argument (the most widely discussed version of which was advanced and defended by Frank Jackson). These arguments highlight the explanatory gap from the physical (which, if materialism is true, should constitute everything that exists, including consciousness) to phenomenal mental states, the principal impossibility to explain the latter by the former, and from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Interactional expertise and embodiment. Selinger, Evan, Dreyfus, Hubert & Harry Collins - 2007 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 38 (4):722-740.
    In this four part exchange, Evan Selinger starts by stating that Collins’s empirical evidence in respect of linguistic socialization and its bearing on artificial intelligence and expertise is valuable; it advances philosophical and sociological understanding of the relationship between knowledge and language. Nevertheless, he argues that Collins mischaracterizes the data under review and thereby misrepresents how knowledge is acquired and understates the extent to which expert knowers are embodied. Selinger reconstructs the case for the importance of the body in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Pathways to sociopathy: Twin analyses offer direction.Nancy L. Segal - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (3):574-575.
    Understanding the bases of complex behavioral phenotypes, such as sociopathy, is assisted by an evolutionary approach, in addition to other theoretical perspectives. Unraveling genetic and environmental factors underlying variant forms of sociopathy remains a key challenge for behavioral science investigators. Twin research methods (e.g., longitudinal analyses; twins reared apart) offer informative means of assessing novel hypotheses relevant to sociopathic behaviors.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Metatheory of animal behavior.Erwin M. Segal - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):386-387.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Verisimilitude and Belief Revision. With a Focus on the Relevant Element Account.Gerhard Schurz - 2011 - Erkenntnis 75 (2):203-221.
    The expansion or revision of false theories by true evidence does not always increase their verisimilitude. After a comparison of different notions of verisimilitude the relation between verisimilitude and belief expansion or revision is investigated within the framework of the relevant element account. We are able to find certain interesting conditions under which both the expansion and the revision of theories by true evidence is guaranteed to increase their verisimilitude.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • The strategy of optimality revisited.Paul J. H. Schoemaker - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (2):237-245.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The quest for optimality: A positive heuristic of science?Paul J. H. Schoemaker - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (2):205-215.
    This paper examines the strengths and weaknesses of one of science's most pervasive and flexible metaprinciples;optimalityis used to explain utility maximization in economics, least effort principles in physics, entropy in chemistry, and survival of the fittest in biology. Fermat's principle of least time involves both teleological and causal considerations, two distinct modes of explanation resting on poorly understood psychological primitives. The rationality heuristic in economics provides an example from social science of the potential biases arising from the extreme flexibility of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Theories and human behavior.Morton L. Schagrin - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):536-536.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Redescribing development.Ellin Kofsky Scholnick - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):727-728.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Relevant deduction.Gerhard Schurz - 1991 - Erkenntnis 35 (1-3):391 - 437.
    This paper presents an outline of a new theory of relevant deduction which arose from the purpose of solving paradoxes in various fields of analytic philosophy. In distinction to relevance logics, this approach does not replace classical logic by a new one, but distinguishes between relevance and validity. It is argued that irrelevant arguments are, although formally valid, nonsensical and even harmful in practical applications. The basic idea is this: a valid deduction is relevant iff no subformula of the conclusion (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   84 citations  
  • Reviews. [REVIEW]Alfred Schramm - 1979 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 30 (1):90-93.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Probabilistic truthlikeness, content elements, and meta-inductive probability optimization.Gerhard Schurz - 2021 - Synthese 199 (3-4):6009-6037.
    The paper starts with the distinction between conjunction-of-parts accounts and disjunction-of-possibilities accounts to truthlikeness. In Sect. 3, three distinctions between kinds of truthlikeness measures are introduced: comparative versus numeric t-measures, t-measures for qualitative versus quantitative theories, and t-measures for deterministic versus probabilistic truth. These three kinds of truthlikeness are explicated and developed within a version of conjunctive part accounts based on content elements. The focus lies on measures of probabilistic truthlikeness, that are divided into t-measures for statistical probabilities and single (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Methodology and finance.Reinhard H. Schmidt - 1982 - Theory and Decision 14 (4):391-413.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is there a choice in “Hobson's choice”?Arnold B. Scheibel - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):418-419.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Classical realism, Freud and human nature in international relations.Robert Schuett - 2010 - History of the Human Sciences 23 (2):21-46.
    Classical realism is enjoying a renaissance in the study of international relations. It is well known that the analytical and normative international-political thought of early 20th-century classical realists is based on assumptions about human nature. Yet current knowledge of these assumptions remains limited. This article therefore revisits and examines the nature and intellectual roots of the human nature assumptions of three truly consequential classical realists. The analysis shows — similar to the causa Hans J. Morgenthau — that the human nature (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Approaches to reduction.Kenneth F. Schaffner - 1967 - Philosophy of Science 34 (2):137-147.
    Four current accounts of theory reduction are presented, first informally and then formally: (1) an account of direct theory reduction that is based on the contributions of Nagel, Woodger, and Quine, (2) an indirect reduction paradigm due to Kemeny and Oppenheim, (3) an "isomorphic model" schema traceable to Suppes, and (4) a theory of reduction that is based on the work of Popper, Feyerabend, and Kuhn. Reference is made, in an attempt to choose between these schemas, to the explanation of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   228 citations  
  • Current questions for the science of behavior.Kenneth M. Sayre - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):535-535.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Some gaps in Grünbaum's critique of psychoanalysis.Irwin Savodnik - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):257-257.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Popper’s Principle of Transference.Husain Sarkar - 1978 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 16 (4):363-371.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Popper's Principle of Transference: A Conjecture Refuted.Husain Sarkar - 1978 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 16 (4):363-371.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark