Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Towards a theory of openness to criticism.Tom Settle, I. C. Jarvie & Joseph Agassi - 1974 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 4 (1):83-90.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Liberal Point of View.Penny Enslin - 1984 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 16 (2):1-9.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Bunge Nevertheless.Joseph Agassi - 2013 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 43 (4):542-562.
    Mario Bunge offers here a political philosophy and a view of current politics as judged by his vision of an integrated democracy that is thoroughly green, quasi-communalist, participatory, and quasi-socialist; all enterprises there belong to their workers. He tempers his egalitarianism with some meritocracy. His vision is impracticable but deserves examination.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Plato and democracy’s ambiguous beauty : the tension between philosophy and democracy.Alexandre Franco de Sá - 2017 - Archai: Revista de Estudos Sobre as Origens Do Pensamento Ocidental 19:15-32.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Against Epistocracy.Paul Gunn - 2019 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 31 (1):26-82.
    In Against Democracy, Jason Brennan argues that public ignorance undermines the legitimacy of democracy because, to the extent that ignorant voters make bad policy choices, they harm their own and one another’s interests. The solution, he thinks, is epistocracy, which would leave policy decisions largely in the hands of social-scientific experts or voters who pass tests of political knowledge. However, Brennan fails to explain why we should think that these putative experts are sufficiently knowledgeable to avoid making errors as damaging (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • The Austrian School of Economics and Ordoliberalism – Socio-Economic Order.Anna Jurczuk, Michał Moszyński & Piotr Pysz - 2019 - Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric 57 (1):105-121.
    The scientific aim of the paper is to juxtapose the views on economic order developed by the leading representatives of two schools of liberal thinking – German ordoliberal Walter Eucken and the Austrian economist Friedrich August von Hayek. The first scholar opted for deliberately constructed competitive economic order, the second one advocates for allowing the social institutions to emerge and evolve spontaneously. The analysis proves the similarity of both theories in regard to the significance of principles of an economic order (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Open Society and the Democracy to Come: Bergson, Deleuze and Guattari.Bruce Baugh - 2016 - Deleuze and Guatarri Studies 10 (3):352-366.
    In Bergsonism, Deleuze refers to Bergson's concept of an ‘open society’, which would be a ‘society of creators’ who gain access to the ‘open creative totality’ through acting and creating. Deleuze and Guattari's political philosophy is oriented toward the goal of such an open society. This would be a democracy, but not in the sense of the rule of the actually existing people, but the rule of ‘the people to come,’ for in the actually existing situation, such a people is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • 50 Key Sociologists: The Contemporary Theorists.John Scott - 2007 - Routledge.
    Fifty Key Sociologists: The Contemporary Theorists covers the life, work, ideas and impact of some of the most important thinkers in this discipline. Concentrating on figures writing predominantly in the second half of the twentieth century, such as Zygmunt Bauman, Pierre Bourdieu, Judith Butler, Michel Foucault and Claude Le;vi-Strauss, each entry includes: · full cross-referencing · a further reading section · biographical data · key works and ideas · critical assessment. Clearly presented in an easy-to-navigate A-Z format, this accessible reference (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Popper's theory of the closed society conflicts with his theory of research.John Wettersten - 2007 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 37 (2):185-209.
    Popper's theory of the attraction of closed societies conflicts with his theory of research: the former sees rational thought as contrary to man's nature, whereas the latter sees it as an innate psychological process. This conflict arose because Popper developed a theory of the movement from the closed society—Heimat—to civilized society, which sees civilized society as a burden, before he adapted Selz's view of directed thought processes as problem solving, which sees rationality as natural. Rejecting the earlier view and retaining (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • An Unacknowledged Adversary: Carl Schmitt, Joseph Schumpeter, and the Classical Doctrine of Democracy.JanaLee Cherneski - 2017 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 29 (4):447-472.
    ABSTRACTIn Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy, Schumpeter contrasted his definition of democracy against what he called its “Classical Doctrine.” Received scholarly wisdom holds either that the classical doctrine had no real historical embodiments, or that it is a composite of historical arguments pieced together only so that Schumpeter could knock them down. Arguably, however, Schumpeter actually drew the classical doctrine from a very real source: Carl Schmitt.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Introduction.I. C. Jarvie & Jeremy Shearmur - 1996 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 26 (4):445-451.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Scientificalization and Vulgarization of Marxism in the 20th Century: A Critical Analysis on K. Popper's Critique of Marxism.Chang Fan - 2013 - Open Journal of Philosophy 3 (4):475.
    Marxism was indeed vulgarized due to scientism in the 20th century, which even limits the development of Chinese social theories nowadays. This paper put forward the idea that it was serious misunderstanding to interpret Marx as prophet or inventor like empiricists who regard finding out eternal laws as the goal of science. In fact, Marx did not propose any so-called “natural laws of historical development”. He articulated that the only thing worth to do was to take note of what happened (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Arguing with the enemy: A dialectical approach to justifying political liberalism.Andreas H. Hvidsten - 2018 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 44 (8):822-842.
    I consider the problem of political pluralism for political liberalism: that not everybody agrees on fundamental political principles. I critically examine three defenses of liberal principles in situations of political pluralism—the realist defense, the pragmatic defense, and Gerald Gaus’ “justificatory liberalism”—all of which I find wanting. Instead, I propose a dialectical approach to justifying political liberalism. A dialectical approach is based on engaging contradictory positions through conceptual investigation of key concepts claimed by both sides. Through such dialectical engagement, I seek (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • El juicio de Sócrates desde el punto de vista ateniense.Morgens Herman Hansen - 2016 - Universitas Philosophica 33 (67):17-52.
    Este estudio reconstruye el juicio de Sócrates, especialmente, el caso levantado por los acusadores. La primera parte es una discusión sobre las fuentes que tenemos disponibles para reconstruir el juicio, especialmente el análisis de Jenofonte en Memorabilia. La segunda parte reconstruye el juicio basados en una nueva evaluación de las fuentes. La tercera parte discute los aspectos políticos del juicio, y argumenta que haber levantado acusaciones políticas contra Sócrates no era necesariamente una infracción a la amnistía del 403. Más aún, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Technological Conspiracies: Comte, Technology, and Spiritual Despotism.Lawrence Quill - 2016 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 28 (1):89-111.
    ABSTRACTWhile there have been numerous critiques of the ideology of technology, it is useful to situate technology within both a liberal and a conspiratorial framework. The early work of Auguste Comte offers an ideal vehicle for this kind of analysis. Liberalism’s embrace of technology is developed in Comte to produce a theory of scientific and technical elites intent on reinventing society and the individual. This “technological conspiracy” reads very much like elements of a Silicon Valley manifesto describing the cyber-utopia of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Cultural evolution.Robert Artigiani - 1987 - World Futures 23 (1):93-121.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The advantage of theft over honest toil.Joseph Agassi - 2009 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 39 (3):507-526.
    Gregory Landini offers a new and an illuminating reading of Ludwig Wittgenstein’s idea about his own innovation: it is the invention of a notation that removes the mystery from all theorems of logic and of mathematics as it renders their proofs part of their wordings. This makes all theorems in principle as boring as “all four-legged animals are animals.” This idea is Wittgenstein’s doctrine of showing. It is worthless; yet, as Landini shows, every time Wittgenstein offered an elaboration on it, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Moral epistemology and totalitarianism: reflections on Arendt, Bauman, Bernstein, and Rorty.Salura Merily - manuscript
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How Do We Learn from Argument?: Toward an Account of the Logic of Problems.Terry M. Goode & John R. Wettersten - 1982 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 12 (4):673-689.
    From the pre-Socratics to the present, one primary aim of philosophy has been to learn from arguments. Philosophers have debated whether we could indeed do this, but they have by and large agreed on how we would use arguments if learning from argument was at all possible. They have agreed that we could learn from arguments either by starting with true premises and validly deducing further statements which must also be true and therefore constitute new knowledge, or that we could (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations