Switch to: References

Citations of:

The Philosophy of Karl Popper

Open Court Publishing Company (1974)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Deconstructing, and reconstructing, Popper.Antony Flew - 1990 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 4 (1-2):155-172.
    RELATIVISM AND THE SOCIAL SCIENCES by Ernest Gellner Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985. 200 pp., £25, £8.50 (paper) Gellner assails Wittgenstein's putative legitimation of the relativistic assumption that ?forms of life?; are autonomous and ultimate, mutually incommunicable, and immune to external criticism. Gellner's view is used here to defend a reconstructed Popperian position against all comers, including Gellner. The tactic is to attack the Cartesian presuppositions Popper implicitly shares with the whole Logical Positivist tradition, arguing that these cannot even be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • W.W. Bartley, III 1934–1990.Angelo M. Petroni - 1990 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 4 (4):737-742.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Popper's theory of deductive inference and the concept of a logical constant.Peter Schroeder-Heister - 1984 - History and Philosophy of Logic 5 (1):79-110.
    This paper deals with Popper's little-known work on deductive logic, published between 1947 and 1949. According to his theory of deductive inference, the meaning of logical signs is determined by certain rules derived from ?inferential definitions? of those signs. Although strong arguments have been presented against Popper's claims (e.g. by Curry, Kleene, Lejewski and McKinsey), his theory can be reconstructed when it is viewed primarily as an attempt to demarcate logical from non-logical constants rather than as a semantic foundation for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • (1 other version)Creative product and creative process in science and art.Larry Briskman - 1980 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 23 (1):83 – 106.
    The main aim of this essay is to propose and develop a product?oriented, non?psychologistic, approach to scientific and artistic creativity. I first argue that the central problem is that of answering the question: how is creativity possible? Traditional approaches to this question tend to locate creativity primarily in some special psychological processes or traits, or in some special creative act. Some general arguments against such an approach are developed, and it is suggested that creativity ought primarily to be located in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Normative epistemology and naturalized epistemology.Harold I. Brown - 1988 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 31 (1):53 – 78.
    A number of philosophers have argued that a naturalized epistemology cannot be normative, and thus that the norms that govern science cannot themselves be established empirically. Three arguments for this conclusion are here developed and then responded to on behalf of naturalized epistemology. The response is developed in three stages. First, if we view human knowers as part of the natural world, then the attempt to establish epistemic norms that are immune to scientific evaluation faces difficulties that are at least (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Hermeneutics and psychoanalysis.Robert L. Woolfolk - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):265-266.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Species of thought: A comment on evolutionary epistemology.David Sloan Wilson - 1990 - Biology and Philosophy 5 (1):37-62.
    The primary outcome of natural selection is adaptation to an environment. The primary concern of epistemology is the acquistion of knowledge. Evolutionary epistemology must therefore draw a fundamental connection between adaptation and knowledge. Existing frameworks in evolutionary epistemology do this in two ways; (a) by treating adaptation as a form of knowledge, and (b) by treating the ability to acquire knowledge as a biologically evolved adaptation. I criticize both frameworks for failing to appreciate that mental representations can motivate behaviors that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Sind Ludwigs Chancengewichtungen propensities im Sinne Poppers?Ursula Wegener - 1980 - Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 11 (1):80-85.
    Eine Besonderheit der propensity-Theorie von Popper liegt darin, daß in ihr - im Gegensatz zu anderen Wahrscheinlichkeitstheorien - die Versuchsbedingungen explizit als Argument in der Wahrscheinlichkeitsfunktion erscheinen. Diese Besonderheit teilt sie mit der Ludwigschen Wahrscheinlichkeitstheorie. Diese Gemeinsamkeit legt die Frage nahe, ob sich aus dem Ludwigschen Formalismus die drei Bedingungen herleiten lassen, die nach Popper aus einer adäquaten Axiomatisierung einer propensity-Theorie folgen müssen. Diese Frage ist um so interessanter, als nach Keuth [1] zwei der Adäquatsbedingungen im Widerspruch zu Poppers eigener (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Psychoanalysis: Conventional wisdom, self knowledge, or inexact science.Murray L. Wax - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):264-265.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ecology and learning: Some historical and analytical perspectives.Edward A. Wasserman - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):183-184.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Early Freud, late Freud, conflict and intentionality.Paul L. Wachtel - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):263-264.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reciprocal interaction in sleep cycle control: Description, yes; explanation, no.Paul A. M. van Dongen - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):424-425.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ascending cholinergic and serotonergic control of the electrocorticogram: Do I see a ghost?C. H. Vanderwolf - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):423-424.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • My two 'difficulties'.Charlene Tan - 2004 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 38 (4):639–662.
    I shall respond to Michael Hand’s rejoinder in respect of the two ‘difficulties’ he has identified with my arguments.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Propensity representations of probability.Patrick Suppes - 1987 - Erkenntnis 26 (3):335 - 358.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Grünbaum, homosexuality, and contemporary psychoanalysis.Frederick Suppe - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):261-262.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Transference: One of Freud's basic discoveries.Hans H. Strupp - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):260-261.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Human understanding and scientific validation.Anthony Storr - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):259-260.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • State control: Changing tools and language.M. Steriade - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):421-423.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Critical rationalism and engineering: ontology.Mark Staples - 2014 - Synthese 191 (10):2255-2279.
    Engineering is often said to be ‘scientific’, but the nature of knowledge in engineering is different to science. Engineering has a different ontological basis—its theories address different entities and are judged by different criteria. In this paper I use Popper’s three worlds ontological framework to propose a model of engineering theories, and provide an abstract logical view of engineering theories analogous to the deductive-nomological view of scientific theories. These models frame three key elements from definitions of engineering: requirements, designs of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Science without reduction.Helmut F. Spinner - 1973 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 16 (1-4):16 – 94.
    The aim of this essay is a criticism of reductionism ? both in its ?static? interpretation (usually referred to as the layer model or level?picture of science) and in its ?dynamic? interpretation (as a theory of the growth of scientific knowledge), with emphasis on the latter ? from the point of view of Popperian fallibilism and Feyerabendian pluralism, but without being committed to the idiosyncrasies of these standpoints. In both aspects of criticism, the rejection is based on the proposal of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Are free associations necessarily contaminated?Donald P. Spence - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):259-259.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Six things Popper would like biologists not to ignore: In memoriam, Karl Raimund Popper, 1902–1994.Tom Settle - 1996 - Biology and Philosophy 11 (2):141-159.
    To honour the memory of Sir Karl Popper, I put forward six elements of his philosophy which might be of particular interest to biologists and to philosophers of biology and which I think Popper would like them not to ignore, even if they disagree with him. They are: the primacy of problems; the criticizability of metaphysics (and thus the dubiousness of materialism); how downward causation might be real; how norms should matter to scientists; why dogmatism should be avoided; how genuine (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The idea of rationality and its relationship to social science: Comments on Popper's philosophy of the social sciences.Michael Schmid - 1988 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 31 (4):451 – 469.
    Popper has proposed a ?theory of situational rationality? as a basis for the social sciences. This theory of rational action is reconstructed and its methodological and substantial implications discussed. It is shown that methodologically Popper's idea of rational action leads to a version of theoretical instrumentalism which is incompatible with his general philosophy of science, and that substantially it implies an unacceptable theory of social institutions. Instrumentalism can be avoided by a more contentful theory of human action encompassing ?non?rational? or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Strong group-level traits and selection-transmission thickets.Jeffrey C. Schank - 2014 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 37 (3):272-273.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Some gaps in Grünbaum's critique of psychoanalysis.Irwin Savodnik - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):257-257.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the significance of the revised reciprocal-interaction model.K. Sakai - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):417-418.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Grünbaum on psychoanalysis: Where do we go from here?Michael Ruse - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):256-257.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Research guiding principles in modern physics: Case studies in elementary particle physics.K. Gavroglu - 1976 - Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 7 (2):223-248.
    Summary Some case studies in elementary particle physics are presented in this work, that can be used for the critical appraisal of specific criteria which were proposed to account for the development of Heisenberg's work. It is attempted to define the philosophical problems associated with and emerging from the structures of theories, rather than analyse the philosophical aspects of concepts used in elementary particle physics. This necessitates the discussion of the relationship between theory and experiment, and the role of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Towards an evolutionary pragmatics of science.Asher Idan & Aharon Kantorovich - 1985 - Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 16 (1):47-66.
    Fundamentismus und Skeptizismus-Anarchismus sind zwei entgegengesetzte Positionen in der traditionellen Erkenntnistheorie und in der modernen Wissenschaftstheorie. Zwischen ihnen gibt es einen dritten Standpunkt, den Evolutionismus. Beispiele sind zwei neuere Arbeiten von Putnam und Stegmüller . Im Gegensatz zum logisch-statischen Fundamentismus berücksichtigt der Evolutionismus auch dynamische und naturalistische Ansätze. Stegmüller folgend entlehnen wir in der vorliegenden Untersuchung aus der Sprachphilosophie pragmatische Gesichtspunkte, um die logische Syntax und Semantik, die Werkzeuge des Fundamentismus, zu ersetzen. Wir zeigen die Kraft der Pragmatik bei der (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • ‘Total evidence’ in phylogenetic systematics.Olivier Rieppel - 2009 - Biology and Philosophy 24 (5):607-622.
    Taking its clues from Popperian philosophy of science, cladistics adopted a number of assumptions of the empiricist tradition. These include the identification of a dichotomy between observation reports and theoretical statements and its subsequent abandonment on the basis of the insight that all observation reports are theory-laden. The neglect of the ‘context of discovery’, which is the step of theory (hypothesis) generation. The emphasis on coherentism in the ‘context of justification’, which is the step of evaluation of the relative merits (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Grünbaum's critique of clinical psychoanalytic evidence: A sheep in wolf's clothing?Morton F. Reiser - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):255-256.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Popperian Image of Science.Gerard Radnitzky - 1976 - Annals of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science 5 (1):3-19.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Economics of Scientific Progress.Gerard Radnitzky - 1987 - Annals of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science 7 (2):85-99.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Predicting overt behavior versus predicting hidden states.Karl Popper - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):254-255.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Is there a “two-cultures” model for psychoanalysis?George H. Pollock - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):253-254.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How (not) to write the history of pragmatist philosophy of science?Sami Pihlström - 2008 - Perspectives on Science 16 (1):26-69.
    This survey article discusses the pragmatist tradition in twentieth century philosophy of science. Pragmatism, originating with Charles Peirce's writings on the pragmatic maxim in the 1870s, is a background both for scientific realism and, via the views of William James and John Dewey, for the relativist and/or constructivist forms of neopragmatism that have often been seen as challenging the very ideas of scientific rationality and objectivity. The paper shows how the issue of realism arises in pragmatist philosophy of science and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Campbell's Blind Variation in the Evolution of an Ideology and Popper's World 3.Ray Scott Percival - 1997 - Philosophica 60 (2).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Philosophers against “truth”: The cases of Harreacute and Laudan.A. Paya - 1995 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 9 (3):255-284.
    The criticisms levelled at the notion of truth by an anti-realist and an entity-realist are critically examined. The upshot of the discussion will be that whilst neither of the two anti-truth philosophers have succeeded in establishing their cases against truth, for entity-realists to reject the notion of truth is to throw out the baby with the bath water: entity-realism without the notion of correspondence truth will degenerate into anti-realism.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The persistence of the “exegetical myth”.Alessandro Pagnini - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):252-252.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Is Freudian psychoanalytic theory really falsifiable?Mark A. Notturno & Paul R. McHugh - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):250-252.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Vasotocin: Neurohumoral control of the reciprocal-interaction model?J. R. Normanton - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):416-417.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Popper and prescriptive methodology.Nicholas Tilley - 1993 - Metaphilosophy 24 (1-2):155-166.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cultural 'demons' as future builders.Massimo Negrotti - 2013 - AI and Society 28 (1):65-73.
    Usually, the shape of the future is seen as the result of a cultural flow that, according to some privileged cultural variable, like technology, goes undisturbed towards its own outcome. This is a quite naive attitude that has been very rarely successful. Both conventional technology and technology of the artificial show that, within culture, ‘demons’ are always active trying to exploit or even bypass standards in order to give birth to unexpected novelties. This is true within the pure technology area (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Sense perception and the reality of the world.Peter Munz - 1988 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 2 (1):65-77.
    THE EVIDENCE OF THE SENSES: A REALISTIC THEORY OF PERCEPTION by David Kelley Baton Rouge and London: Louisiana State University Press, 1986. 286 pp., $24.95.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Book reviews. [REVIEW]Harvey Mullan & Justin Leiber - 1989 - Philosophical Psychology 2 (2):241-246.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What will we gain from an ecological approach to learning? Another ethologist's view.Helmut C. Mueller - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):182-183.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • When is a “center” not a “center”? When it's “anatomically distributed”: Prospects for a “diffuse REM center”.Peter J. Morgane - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):414-415.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Proposed model of postural atonia in a decerebrate cat.S. Mori & Y. Ohta - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):415-416.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Are cholinergic, noradrenergic, and serotonergic neurons sufficient for understanding REM sleep control?Jaime M. Monti - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):413-414.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark