Switch to: References

Citations of:

Philosophical Papers: Volume 1, Mathematics, Matter and Method

New York: Cambridge University Press (1979)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Scientific Revolutions and the Explosion of Scientific Evidence.Ludwig Fahrbach - 2017 - Synthese 194 (12):5039-5072.
    Scientific realism, the position that successful theories are likely to be approximately true, is threatened by the pessimistic induction according to which the history of science is full of suc- cessful, but false theories. I aim to defend scientific realism against the pessimistic induction. My main thesis is that our current best theories each enjoy a very high degree of predictive success, far higher than was enjoyed by any of the refuted theories. I support this thesis by showing that both (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • (1 other version)Can Indispensability‐Driven Platonists Be (Serious) Presentists?Sam Baron - 2013 - Theoria 79 (3):153-173.
    In this article I consider what it would take to combine a certain kind of mathematical Platonism with serious presentism. I argue that a Platonist moved to accept the existence of mathematical objects on the basis of an indispensability argument faces a significant challenge if she wishes to accept presentism. This is because, on the one hand, the indispensability argument can be reformulated as a new argument for the existence of past entities and, on the other hand, if one accepts (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The philosophy and physics of affecting the past.Huw Price - 1984 - Synthese 61 (3):299 - 323.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Two responses to Laura: Evers, and Phillips.. New frontiers or crossing the Bounds of inference?Colin W. Evers - 1988 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 20 (1):70–75.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)L’;épistémologie mathématique de Gonseth dans la perspective du pragmatisme de Peirce.Gerhard Heinzmann - 1990 - Dialectica 44 (3-4):279-286.
    RésuméSelon un pragmatiste, la réflexion du philosophe porte sur le lien entre la construction et la description des objets mathématiques. Grâce à sa conception?un raisonnement dit ≫theorematique≪, Peirce a réussi à etablir ľesquisse?une interprétation pragmatique?une structure mathématique. Cette dernière reste néanmoins vague quant à la catégoricité de la structure. – lci, il est utile de recourir à Gonseth et & dcar;analyser sa reconstruction?un système axiomatique: la genèse logique?une structure selon les principes de ľidonéisme correspond en effet au programme de Peirce, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The rationale behind Pierre Duhem's natural classification.Sindhuja Bhakthavatsalam - 2015 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 51:11-21.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Justifying Sociological Knowledge: From Realism to Interpretation.Isaac Reed - 2008 - Sociological Theory 26 (2):101-129.
    In the context of calls for "postpositivist" sociology, realism has emerged as a powerful and compelling epistemology for social science. In transferring and transforming scientific realism --a philosophy of natural science--into a justificatory discourse for social science, realism splits into two parts: a strict, highly naturalistic realism and a reflexive, more mediated, and critical realism. Both forms of realism, however, suffer from conceptual ambiguities, omissions, and elisions that make them an inappropriate epistemology for social science. Examination of these problems in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Force and Objectivity: On Impact, Form, and Receptivity to Nature in Science and Art.Eli Lichtenstein - 2019 - Dissertation, University of Michigan
    I argue that scientific and poetic modes of objectivity are perspectival duals: 'views' from and onto basic natural forces, respectively. I ground this analysis in a general account of objectivity, not in terms of either 'universal' or 'inter-subjective' validity, but as receptivity to basic features of reality. Contra traditionalists, bare truth, factual knowledge, and universally valid representation are not inherently valuable. But modern critics who focus primarily on the self-expressive aspect of science are also wrong to claim that our knowledge (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Two types of empirical adequacy: a partial structures approach.John M. Dukich - 2013 - Synthese 190 (14):2801-2820.
    The notion of empirical adequacy has received recent philosophical attention, especially within the framework of the semantic approach. Empirical adequacy, as explicated in the semantic approach, concerns the relationship between empirical substructures and some phenomena. The aim here is to differentiate this notion of empirical adequacy from one concerning the relationship between data and phenomena. Distinguishing each notion of empirical adequacy emphasizes different aspects of scientific practice—one concerning theory-development from the basis of an established theory, the other concerning theory-development from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Truthmaker Indispensability Argument.Sam Baron - 2013 - Synthese 190 (12):2413-2427.
    Recently, nominalists have made a case against the Quine–Putnam indispensability argument for mathematical Platonism by taking issue with Quine’s criterion of ontological commitment. In this paper I propose and defend an indispensability argument founded on an alternative criterion of ontological commitment: that advocated by David Armstrong. By defending such an argument I place the burden back onto the nominalist to defend her favourite criterion of ontological commitment and, furthermore, show that criterion cannot be used to formulate a plausible form of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The architecture of complexity: A new blueprint.Peter Turney - 1989 - Synthese 79 (3):515 - 542.
    The logic of scientific discovery is now a concern of computer scientists, as well as philosophers. In the computational approach to inductive inference, theories are treated as algorithms (computer programs), and the goal is to find the simplest algorithm that can generate the given data. Both computer scientists and philosophers want a measure of simplicity, such that simple theories are more likely to be true than complex theories. I attempt to provide such a measure here. I define a measure of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Is Pickering's "pragmatic realism" viable?Dan Mcarthur - 2003 - Dialectica 57 (1):71–88.
    In his book The Mangle of Practice and in other writings, Andrew Pickering purports to resolve the question of scientific realism by recasting the debate in terms of his own view “pragmatic” or “performative” realism. This view is informed by a constructivist view of scientific practice. Therefore it is characterised by Pickering as a species of anti‐realism that claims to take due account of the both the objective and pragmatic aspects of certain versions of scientific realism. This paper analyses Pickering's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Instrumentalizing and Naturalizing Social Ontology: Replies to Lohse and Little.Richard Lauer - 2021 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 51 (1):24-39.
    This article addresses Simon Lohse’s and Daniel Little’s responses to my article “Is Social Ontology Prior to Social Scientific Methodology?.” In that article, I present a pragmatic and deflationary view of the priority of social ontology to social science methodology where social ontology is valued for its ability to promote empirical success and not because it yields knowledge of what furnishes the social world. First, in response to Lohse, I argue that my view is compatible with a role for ontological (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Great Philosophy: Discovery, Invention, and the Uses of Error.Christopher Norris - 2014 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 22 (3):349-379.
    In this essay I consider what is meant by the description ‘great’ philosophy and then offer some broadly applicable criteria by which to assess candidate thinkers or works. On the one hand are philosophers in whose case the epithet, even if contested, is not grossly misconceived or merely the product of doctrinal adherence on the part of those who apply it. On the other are those – however gifted, acute, or technically adroit – to whom its application is inappropriate because (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Measurement in Carnap's late Philosophy of Science.Vadim Batitsky - 2000 - Dialectica 54 (2):87-108.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations