Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. A thousand pleasures are not worth a single pain: The compensation argument for Schopenhauer's pessimism.Byron Simmons - 2021 - European Journal of Philosophy 29 (1):120-136.
    Pessimism is, roughly, the view that life is not worth living. In chapter 46 of the second volume of The World as Will and Representation, Arthur Schopenhauer provides an oft-neglected argument for this view. The argument is that a life is worth living only if it does not contain any uncompensated evils; but since all our lives happen to contain such evils, none of them are worth living. The now standard interpretation of this argument (endorsed by Kuno Fischer and Christopher (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Feigl’s ‘Scientific Realism’.Matthias Neuber - 2011 - Philosophy of Science 78 (1):165-183.
    This article considers the evolution of Feigl's attempt at establishing a stable form of scientific realism. I will argue that Feigl's work in that area should be appreciated for two reasons: it represents a telling case against the view of there being an unbridgeable ‘analytic-continental divide’ in the context of twentieth-century philosophy; it contradicts the idea that scientific realism is at odds with logical empiricism. It will be shown that Feigl developed his scientific realist position from within the logical empiricists’ (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Ilse Schneider (and Alois Riehl) on the Space-Time Problem in Kant and Einstein: New Perspectives on Neo-Kantianism and Positivism.Rudolf Meer - 2024 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 14 (2):508-526.
    In her 1921 book, The Space-Time Problem in Kant and Einstein, Ilse Schneider examines the foundations and consequences of the theory of relativity from an epistemological perspective. Beyond addressing detailed questions of early 1920s physics, it is a programmatic attempt to reconcile Kant’s transcendental idealism with Albert Einstein’s physics. The Kantian background puts the book in direct competition with Ernst Cassirer’s book Einstein’s Theory of Relativity, published in the same year. Schneider’s approach was largely ignored in the research compared with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Positive Foundations of the Axiological Aspect of Historical-Philosophical Research.Aleksandr A. Lvov - 2019 - Russian Journal of Philosophical Sciences 62 (10):55-67.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Zwischen Universitätsreformen und katholischer Renaissance.Josef Hlade & Rudolf Meer - 2022 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 99 (2):293-328.
    With the first edition of the Philosophical Criticism, published in the 1870s and 1880s, Alois Riehl became the founder and most important representative of Realistic Criticism, and emerged as one of the leading figures in German-speaking philosophy at the turn of the century. In 1901, he applied for a chair at the Faculty of Philosophy at the University of Vienna. In the appointment procedure for the succession to Ernst Mach, he was chosen by the committee with the recommendation unico loco, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • About the harm of science to life. Science and education as key philosophical issues in the works of Friedrich Nietzsche and Karl Jaspers.Mirko Wischke - 2005 - Sententiae 12 (1):70-80.
    The author analyzes the views of Friedrich Nietzsche and Karl Jaspers on the essence and goals of science. According to Nietzsche, scientific interest has no clear goal and ultimately leads to nihilism. Nietzsche criticizes science for the limitless accumulation of information, which blinds and prevents the evaluation of the achieved results. For Jaspers, the desire for knowledge, rooted in human nature, not only has unforeseen consequences, but also does not provide an answer to the question of the essence of science (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Different Theoretical Layers of The Civilizing Process: A Response to Goudsblom and Kilminster & Wouters.Benjo Maso - 1995 - Theory, Culture and Society 12 (3):127-145.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Neo-Kantianism, Darwinism, and the limits of historical explanation.Evan Clarke - 2021 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 29 (4):590-613.
    This paper looks at the neo-Kantian response to Darwinism as a historical science. I distinguish four responses to this aspect of Darwin’s thought from within the neo-Kantian tradition. The first line of response, represented by August Stadler and Bruno Bauch, views Darwin’s model of historical explanation as a fulfilment of Kant’s criteria of scientific intelligibility. The second, represented by Otto Liebmann, regards historical explanation as intrinsically limited, because it cannot tell us why nature develops as it does. The third line (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark