Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. (1 other version)The moral status of nature : reasons to care for the natural world.Lars Samuelsson - 2008 - Dissertation,
    The subject-matter of this essay is the moral status of nature. This subject is dealt with in terms of normative reasons. The main question is if there are direct normative reasons to care for nature in addition to the numerous indirect normative reasons that there are for doing so. Roughly, if there is some such reason, and that reason applies to any moral agent, then nature has direct moral status as I use the phrase. I develop the notions of direct (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Rethinking Representation: the Challenge of Non-humans.Mihnea Tanasescu - 2014 - Australian Journal of Political Science 49 (1).
    This article argues that the standard model of political representation mischaracterises the structure of representation. After surveying the classical types of representation and their application to non-humans, the basic nature of representation is shown to have been unduly centred on interests, responsiveness and unidirectional protocols. It proposes a different structure by drawing inspiration from recent scholarship and developments in political philosophy, as well as the representation of non-human actors. It proposes an ontological grounding of representation in ‘irreducible multiplicity’, and a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Individual or Community? Two Approaches to Ecophilosophy in Practice.David Rothenberg - 1992 - Environmental Values 1 (2):123 - 132.
    Should environmental philosophers – or practical conservationists – focus their attentions on particular living creatures, or on the community of which they, and we, are part? The individualist ethos of the United States is reflected in legislation to protect endangered species in which particular species are portrayed as individuals with rights that must be protected. By contrast, the planning of environmental protection in Norway, exemplified by the Samla Plan for the management of water resources, emphasizes the importance of community integrity, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • When Utilitarians Should Be Virtue Theorists.Dale Jamieson - 2007 - Utilitas 19 (2):160.
    The contrast typically made between utilitarianism and virtue theory is overdrawn. Utilitarianism is a universal emulator: it implies that we should lie, cheat, steal, even appropriate Aristotle, when that is what brings about the best outcomes. In some cases and in some worlds it is best for us to focus as precisely as possible on individual acts. In other cases and worlds it is best for us to be concerned with character traits. Global environmental change leads to concerns about character (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   111 citations  
  • The Threefold Struggle: Pursuing Ecological, Social, and Personal Wellbeing in the Spirit of Daniel Quinn.Andrew Frederick Smith (ed.) - 2022 - SUNY Press.
    We members of settler colonial culture—the latest form of what novelist and cultural critic Daniel Quinn calls Taker culture—are constrained by myriad institutions that leave us with little choice but to engage in practices that are profoundly damaging to the planet, to others, and to ourselves. Our path to living otherwise, Andrew Frederick Smith argues, lies in the threefold struggle, which is inspired by Quinn's focus on the interweaving roots of ecological, social, and personal wellbeing. These three forms of wellbeing (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Justice Through a Multispecies Lens.Danielle Celermajer, Sria Chatterjee, Alasdair Cochrane, Stefanie Fishel, Astrida Neimanis, Anne O’Brien, Susan Reid, Krithika Srinivasan, David Schlosberg & Anik Waldow - 2020 - Contemporary Political Theory 19 (3):475-512.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (1 other version)Feminism, Deep Ecology, and Environmental Ethics.Michael E. Zimmerman - 1987 - Environmental Ethics 9 (1):21-44.
    Deep ecologists have criticized reform environmentalists for not being sufficiently radical in their attempts to curb human exploitation of the nonhuman world. Ecofeminists, however, maintain that deep ecologists, too, are not sufficiently radical, for they have neglected the cmcial role played by patriarchalism in shaping the cultural categories responsible for Western humanity’s domination of Nature. According to eco-feminists, only by replacing those categories-including atomism, hierarchalism, dualism, and androcentrism - can humanity learn to dweIl in harmony with nonhuman beings. After reviewing (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Deep Ecology as an Aesthetic Movement.Tony Lynch - 1996 - Environmental Values 5 (2):147 - 160.
    Many deep ecologists call for a 'new ecological ethic'. If this ethic is meant to be a moral ethic, then deep ecology fails. However if deep ecology is interpreted as an aesthetic movement, then it is both philosophically coherent and practically adequate.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The key of the door.E. P. Brandon - 1979 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 11 (1):23–34.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hunt–Vitell’s General Theory of Marketing Ethics Predicts “Attitude-Behaviour” Gap in Pro-environmental Domain.Laura Zaikauskaitė, Gemma Butler, Nurul F. S. Helmi, Charlotte L. Robinson, Luke Treglown, Dimitrios Tsivrikos & Joseph T. Devlin - 2022 - Frontiers in Psychology 13:732661.
    The inconsistency between pro-environmental attitudes and behaviours, known as the “attitude-behaviour” gap, is exceptionally pronounced in scenarios associated with “green” choice. The current literature offers numerous explanations for the reasons behind the “attitude-behaviour” gap, however, the generalisability of these explanations is complex. In addition, the answer to the question of whether the gap occurs between attitudes and intentions, or intentions and behaviours is also unknown. In this study, we propose the moral dimension as a generalisable driver of the “attitude-behaviour” gap (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Non-human rights: An idealist perspective.T. L. S. Sprigge - 1984 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 27 (1-4):439 – 461.
    The question whether an entity has rights is identified with that as to whether an intrinsic value resides in it which imposes obligations to foster it on those who can appreciate this value. There should be no difficulty in granting that animals have rights in this sense, but what of other natural objects and artifacts? It seems that various inanimate things, such as fine buildings and forests, often possess such intrinsic value, yet since they can only be fully actual in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Human Rights in an Ecological Era.William Aiken - 1992 - Environmental Values 1 (3):191 - 203.
    After presenting a brief history of the idea of a human right to an adequate environment as it has evolved in the United Nations documents, I assess this approach to our moral responsibility with regard to the environment. I argue that although this rights approach has some substantial weaknesses, these are outweighed by such clear advantages as its action-guiding nature and its political potency.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • To act or not to act? Sheltering animals from the wild: A pluralistic account of a conflict between animal and environmental ethics.Bernice Bovenkerk, Frans Stafleu, Ronno Tramper, Jan Vorstenbosch & Frans W. A. Brom - 2003 - Ethics, Place and Environment 6 (1):13 – 26.
    The leading question of this article is whether it is acceptable, from a moral point of view, to take wild animals that are ill out of their natural habitat and temporarily bring them under human control with the purpose of curing them. To this end the so-called 'seal debate' was examined. In the Netherlands, seals that are lost or ill are rescued and taken into shelters, where they are cured and afterwards reintroduced into their natural environment. Recently, this practice has (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Beyond Human Racism.Robyn Eckersley - 1998 - Environmental Values 7 (2):165-182.
    In 'Non-Anthropocentrism? A Killing Objection', Tony Lynch and David Wells argue that any attempt to develop a non-anthropocentric morality must invariably slide back to either anthropocentrism (either weak or strong) or a highly repugnant misanthropy in cases of direct conflict between the survival needs of humans and nonhuman species. This reply argues that their attempt to expose the flaws in non-anthropocentrism deflects attention away from the crux of the ecocentric critique, which can best be understood if we replace the confusing (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Liberation of Humanity and Nature.Eric Katz - 2002 - Environmental Values 11 (4):397-405.
    What does the ' liberation ' of nature mean? In this essay, I use a pragmatic methodology to reject the idea that we need a metaphysical understanding of the nature of nature before we can speak of nature's liberation, and explain the sense of liberation as being the continuation of human non-interference in natural processes. Two real life policy cases are cited as examples: beach restoration on Fire Island and rock climbing in designated wilderness areas.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)Trajectories of green political theory.Andrew Dobson, Sherilyn MacGregor, Douglas Torgerson & Michael Saward - 2009 - Contemporary Political Theory 8 (3):317-350.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Sylvan, Fox and Deep Ecology: A View from the Continental Shelf.Robin Attfield - 1993 - Environmental Values 2 (1):21 - 32.
    Both Richard Sylvan’s trenchant critique of Deep Ecology and Warwick Fox’s illuminating reinterpretation and defence are presented and appraised. Besides throwing light on the nature and the prospects of the defence of Deep Ecology and of its diverse axiological, epistemological and metaphysical strands, the appraisal discloses the range of normative positions open to those who reject anthropocentrism, of which Deep Ecology is no more than one (and, if Fox’s account of its nature is right, may not be one at all). (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Animal justice: The counter‐revolution in natural right and law.John Rodman - 1979 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 22 (1-4):3 – 22.
    The debate over whether human animals are linked by bonds of justice to nonhu-man animals is ancient and has been several times settled. The Roman jurists defined the j us naturae in terms of what nature had taught 'all animals', but Grotius and other natural-law theorists rejected this view and redefined the jus naturae as that which accorded with human nature, thereby founding the 'modern' view which has excluded nonhuman animals from the sphere of justice. This paper examines Grotius's argument (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • (1 other version)Trajectories of green political theory.Michael Saward Andrew Dobson, Sherilyn MacGregor, Douglas Torgerson - 2009 - Contemporary Political Theory 8 (3):317.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A critical overview of environmental ethics.Warwick Fox - 1996 - World Futures 46 (1):1-21.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Natural allies, perennial foes? On the trajectories of feminist and green political thought.Sherilyn MacGregor - 2009 - Contemporary Political Theory 8 (3):329-339.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • On the Rights of Non-Persons.Douglas N. Husak - 1980 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 10 (4):607 - 622.
    Do non-persons have moral rights? I will suppose this question can best be answered by inquiring whether some animals and/or environmental objects have moral rights, for if any non-persons are possessors of rights, animals and/or environmental objects are the most plausible candidates. As so interpreted, this question has received an extraordinary amount of recent attention from philosophers. Arguments have been offered and defended; rebuttals have appeared in print. Yet, so far as I am aware, no one has presented a clear (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is it natural to drive species to extinction?Mark A. Michael - 2005 - Ethics and the Environment 10 (1):49-66.
    : Whether or not extinction caused by human activities is natural depends on which sense of the term 'natural' is under consideration. Given one sense of that term which has some grip on the popular imagination, it is. This suggests that at a minimum environmentalists should be very careful about invoking 'the natural' and related concepts such as 'acting naturally' when they propose moral principles. I argue here for the stronger claim that the 'natural' is either redundant and serves to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Some recent positions in environmental ethics examined.T. L. S. Sprigge - 1991 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 34 (1):107 – 128.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Exploring the Farther Reaches of Commoditization: A Systemic Perspective.David W. Kidner - 2012 - Bulletin of Science, Technology and Society 32 (1):18-30.
    The structures and processes that provide a context favorable to commoditization are sedimented into our lives so that they become taken-for-granted and apparently unproblematic aspects of the cultural scenery. Language, economic “realities,” our styles of thought and categorization, education, the infrastructure we inhabit, and subjectivity itself have all been shaped in ways that make commoditization seem inevitable and even natural. Consequently, the more noticeable excesses of commoditization are the symptoms of a much more pervasive colonization of the world and our (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Natural Justice: From Abstract Rights to Contextualised Needs. [REVIEW]Robyn Eckersley - 1994 - Environmental Values 3 (2):161 - 172.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Muddled Middle: The Search for Ethical Principles to Regulate the Use of Animals in Research.Richard P. Haynes - 1996 - Between the Species 12 (1):6.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark