Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Procreative loss without pregnancy loss: the limitations of fetal-centric conceptions of pregnancy.Hannah Carpenter, Georgia Loutrianakis, Peyton Baker, Tiffany Bystra & Lisa Campo-Engelstein - 2024 - Journal of Medical Ethics 50 (5):310-311.
    In their article, Romanis and Adkins delineate pregnancy loss and procreative loss to show that the former is possible without the latter, as in the case of artificial amnion and placenta technology.1 Here, we are interested in examining the reverse—procreative loss without pregnancy loss—to further tease apart these two types of loss. We discuss two cases: being forced to continue a pregnancy despite fetal demise due to abortion restrictions and choosing to selectively reduce a multifetal pregnancy. Our analysis buttresses the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • AAPT, pregnancy loss and planning ahead.Victoria Adkins & Elizabeth Chloe Romanis - 2024 - Journal of Medical Ethics 50 (5):318-319.
    The commentaries in response to our feature paper1 are indicative of the varied perspectives that can be taken towards artificial amnion and placenta technology (AAPT) and more specifically its relationship with pregnancy (loss). Kennedy rightly argues that empirical research is essential for understanding the experiences of pregnancy loss and AAPT2 and our own advocacy of empirical research is evident in previous work.3–5 Kennedy also acknowledges the current impossibility of researching AAPT experiences since it has not yet been applied in clinical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Addressing or reinforcing injustice? Artificial amnion and placenta technology, loss-sensitive care and racial inequities in preterm birth.Sophie L. Schott, Faith Fletcher, Alice Story & April Adams - 2024 - Journal of Medical Ethics 50 (5):316-317.
    Preterm birth is defined as delivery occurring before 37 weeks gestation.1 Infants born prematurely have increased risks of morbidity and mortality throughout life, especially during the first year. These risks increase as the gestational age at birth decreases.2 Additionally, there are significant racial and ethnic differences in preterm birth rates. In 2022, the rate of preterm birth among non-Hispanic black women was approximately 50% higher than that observed in non-Hispanic white women.1 The outcomes for these infants are also disparate–preterm birth (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Pregnancy loss in the context of AAPT: speculation over substance?Susan Kennedy - 2024 - Journal of Medical Ethics 50 (5):314-315.
    Romanis and Adkins explore the near-term prospect of artificial amnion and placenta technology (AAPT) which is being developed to supplement the gestational process following the premature ending of a pregnancy.1 While fetal-centric narratives prevail in discussions surrounding AAPT, the authors subvert this trend by centering the experience of pregnant persons with respect to pregnancy loss. The overarching aim of their paper is to move beyond a ‘philosophical understanding of pregnancy towards practical-orientated conclusions regarding the care pathways surrounding [AAPT]’ (Romanis and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Overcoming (false) dichotomies to address ethical issues of artificial placentas.Alice Cavolo - 2024 - Journal of Medical Ethics 50 (5):308-309.
    Romanis and Adkins discuss pregnancy loss in relation to artificial amnion and placenta technology (AAPT) for treatment of extremely preterm infants.1 I agree with the authors that AAPT, although it is expected to provide better care for extremely preterm infants, will also be challenging for parents. I, therefore, commend Romanis and Adkins for promoting a more holistic care that includes parents and pregnant persons. However, I believe that they create two false dichotomies, one between the pregnant person/parent and the fetus/child (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Value sensitive design and the artificial placenta.Elizabeth Chloe Romanis, Seppe Segers & Ben D. de Jong - forthcoming - Journal of Medical Ethics.
    Artificial placenta technologies (also termed ‘artificial wombs’) for use in place of conventional neonatal intensive care are increasingly closer to first-in-human use. There is growing ethical interest in partial ectogestation (the use of an artificial placenta to continue gestation of an underdeveloped human entity extra uterum), however, there has been little reflection on the ethical issues in the design of the technology. While some have noted the importance of such reflection, and others have noted that a ‘value sensitive design’ approach (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Pregnancy loss care should not be biased in favour of human gestation.Andrea Bidoli - 2024 - Journal of Medical Ethics 50 (5):312-313.
    In their paper, Romanis and Adkins delve into the potential impact of artificial amnion and placenta technology (AAPT) on cases of pregnancy loss1 that do not involve procreative loss. First, they call for more recognition of the negative feelings a person might have due to the premature end of their pregnant state. They claim that, should AAPT minimise concerns about prematurity as anticipated, individuals might feel pressured to opt for partial ectogestation to preserve their or their fetus’ well-being; moreover, they (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation