Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Would They Follow What has been Laid Down? Cancer Patients' and Healthy Controls' Views on Adherence to Advance Directives Compared to Medical Staff.Stefan Sahm, R. Will & G. Hommel - 2005 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 8 (3):297-305.
    Advance directives are propagated as instruments to maintain patients’ autonomy in case they can no longer decide for themselves. It has been never been examined whether patients’ and healthy persons themselves are inclined to adhere to these documents. Patients’ and healthy persons’ views on whether instructions laid down in advance directives should be followed because that is (or is not) “the right thing to do”, not because one is legally obliged to do so, were studied and compared with that of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Personal Identity and Ethics.David Shoemaker - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    What justifies our holding a person morally responsible for some past action? Why am I justified in having a special prudential concern for some future persons and not others? Why do many of us think that maximizing the good within a single life is perfectly acceptable, but maximizing the good across lives is wrong? In these and other normative questions, it looks like any answer we come up with will have to make an essential reference to personal identity. So, for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Limiting risks by curtailing rights: a response to Dr Ryan.S. Luttrell & A. Sommerville - 1996 - Journal of Medical Ethics 22 (2):100-104.
    It has been argued that the inherent risks of advance directives made by healthy people are disproportionate to the potential benefits, particularly if the directive is implementable in cases of reversible mental incapacity. This paper maintains that the evidence for such a position is lacking. Furthermore, respect for the principle of autonomy requires that individuals be permitted to make risky choices about their own lives as long as these do not impinge on others. Even though health professionals have an obligation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Living wills and substituted judgments: A critical analysis.Jos V. M. Welie - 2001 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 4 (2):169-183.
    In the literature three mechanisms are commonly distinguished to make decisions about the care of incompetent patients: A living will, a substituted judgment by a surrogate (who may or may not hold the power of attorney ), and a best interest judgment. Almost universally, the third mechanism is deemed the worst possible of the three, to be invoked only when the former two are unavailable. In this article, I argue in favor of best interest judgments. The evermore common aversion of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Can identity-relative paternalism shift the focus from the principle of autonomy?Cressida Auckland - 2023 - Journal of Medical Ethics 49 (7):451-452.
    Mill’s proscription that ‘the only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilised community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others’ has become almost axiomatic in bioethics. 1 Bolstered by the rise of patient autonomy during the mid-20th century, Millian conceptions of freedom have become so embedded in bioethical theory, that attempts to justify paternalism have typically involved making one of two claims. Either, they have involved refuting the significance of autonomy as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Use of the welfare-based model in the application of palliative sedation.Su Yan Yap - 2018 - Asian Bioethics Review 10 (1):93-101.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Advance directives.T. Hope - 1996 - Journal of Medical Ethics 22 (2):67-68.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Doctors' authoritarianism in end-of-life treatment decisions. A comparison between Russia, Sweden and Germany.J. Richter - 2001 - Journal of Medical Ethics 27 (3):186-191.
    Objectives—The study was performed in order to investigate how end-of-life decisions are influenced by cultural and sociopolitical circumstances and to explore the compliance of doctors with patient wishesParticipants and measurement—Five hundred and thirty-five physicians were surveyed in Sweden , Germany , and in Russia by a questionnaire. The participants were recruited according to availability and are not representative. The questionnaire is based on the one developed by Molloy and co-workers in Canada which contains three case vignettes about an 82-year-old Alzheimer (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Coercive treatment and autonomy in psychiatry.Manne Sjöstrand & Gert Helgesson - 2008 - Bioethics 22 (2):113–120.
    There are three lines of argument in defence of coercive treatment of patients with mental disorders: arguments regarding (1) societal interests to protect others, (2) the patients' own health interests, and (3) patient autonomy. In this paper, we analyse these arguments in relation to an idealized case, where a person with a mental disorder claims not to want medical treatment for religious reasons. We also discuss who should decide what in situations where patients with mental disorders deny treatment on seemingly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations