Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Analytic philosophy in Japan 1933–2000.Tomohisa Furuta & Takashi Iida - 2022 - Asian Journal of Philosophy 1 (1):1-24.
    Although logical positivism had been known before World War II, it was introduced into academic philosophy in Japan only after it. In this process, the US philosophers who came to Japan in order to participate in American Studies Seminar played an important role. The first generation of Japanese analytic philosophers, who were born in the 1920s and 1930s, began to have some influence in the 1960s, and some of them published original works of high quality in the 1970s. The second (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Prichard vs. Plato: Intuition vs. Reflection.Mark Lebar - 2007 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 33 (sup1):1-32.
    The project of this paper is to address a complaint, by Prichard, against Plato and other ancients, as committing a basic “mistake” in moral philosophy. The basic mistake is in thinking that we are capable of giving reasons for the requirements of duty, rather than directly and immediately apprehending those requirements. Prichard’s argument that this is a mistake consists in an argument that attempts to give reasons for such requirements always fail. He classes those attempts into two kinds, and one (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Prichard vs. Plato: Intuition vs. reflection.Mark Lebar - 2007 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 37 (5):pp. 1-32.
    This paper addresses a complaint, by Prichard, against Plato and other ancients. The charge is that they commit a mistake is in thinking that we are capable of giving reasons for the requirements of duty, rather than directly and immediately apprehending those requirements. I respond in two ways. First, Plato does not make the egregious mistake of substituting interest for duty, and thus giving the wrong kind of reason for duty’s requirements, as Prichard alleges. Second, we should see that the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Decline of Egoism.Robert Shaver - 2022 - Utilitas 34 (3):300-316.
    Sidgwick saw egoism as important and undefeated. Not long afterward, egoism is largely ignored. Immediately after Sidgwick, many arguments were given against egoism – most poor – but one argument deserves attention as both influential and plausible. Call it the “grounds objection.” It has two strands. It objects that there are justifying reasons for action other than that an action will maximize my self-interest. It also objects that sometimes, what makes an action right is a fact other than its maximizing (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Ethical Intuitionism II.J. R. Lucas - 1971 - Philosophy 46 (175):1-11.
    South. So we have agreed to bury intuitionism. Well, I dare say it is right. But we ought to bury some of the grave-diggers too. Some of the things that Ross said are no doubt wrong, or at least misleading: but they are a lot less wrong than most of the things said since the war.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Outline of a theory on the general logical structure of the language of action.Hector Neri Castañeda - 1960 - Theoria 26 (3):151-182.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Moral Motivation: the Practical Philosophy of Wilfrid Sellars. [REVIEW]Michael R. Hicks - 2023 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 31 (5):718-729.
    1. In the preface to his magnum opus, Science and Metaphysics, Wilfrid Sellars describes the final chapter on ‘objectivity and intersubjectivity in ethics’ as ‘the keystone of the argument,’ becaus...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark