Switch to: References

Citations of:

Sextus Empiricus

W. Heinemann Harvard University Press (1961)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Tranquility Without a Stop: Timon, Frag. 68.M. F. Burnyeat - 1980 - Classical Quarterly 30 (01):86-.
    Translation at this stage would be premature, but three variants in line 3 deserve notice, Bury writes Natorp , followed by Brochard , suggested , Wachsmuth prints a colon instead of a comma after It is not surprising that line 3 has attracted emendation. As it stands, it lacks a verb and has to modify an understood existential.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Some notes on sextus empiricus’ method of approaching the téchnai.Rodrigo Pinto de Brito, Alexandre Arantes & Lauro Lane de Morais - 2017 - Archai: Revista de Estudos Sobre as Origens Do Pensamento Ocidental 21:251-279.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • NONEXISTENCE - A comparative-historical analysis of the problem of nonbeing.Michael D. Bakaoukas - 2014 - E-Logos 21 (1):1-25.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A New Answer to an Old Puzzle: Nοεῐν ἁπλῶς.Anna Tigani - 2016 - History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 19 (1):188-211.
    Sextus responds to the Dogmatists’ criticism that the Sceptics cannot investigate Dogmatic theses, formulating his own version of Meno’s puzzle against them. He thus forces them to adopt υοεῐυ ἁπλῶς – a way of thinking that does not carry any commitment to the reality of what someone thinks – as their only solution to the puzzle and as the necessary starting point of their investigation. Nοεῐυ ἁπλῶς avoids Dogmatic assumptions without making use of the Sceptical argumentation that leads to suspension (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Against the Grammarians by Sextus Empiricus: annotated translation, part three.Joseane Mara Prezotto - 2019 - Archai: Revista de Estudos Sobre as Origens Do Pensamento Ocidental 25:1-30.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the possibility of a sceptical technē in Sextus Empiricus' works.Rodrigo Pinto de Brito - 2018 - Prometeus: Filosofia em Revista 11 (28).
    Galen was a prolific writer, mostly important for the development of medicine. However he is not receiving the deserved attention by researchers in Lusophonic world. Here we aim to show why studying Galen’s De Sectis is useful as an external source for comprehending Sextus Empiricus and his empiricism, as well as his exhortation to live in accordance to the ordinary life. Furthermore, in two appendices we offer the main primary sources, and we display a chronology of the physicians mentioned in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Pyrrhonist’s ἀταραξία and φιλανθρωπία.Diego E. Machuca - 2006 - Ancient Philosophy 26 (1):111-126.
    The purpose of the present paper is twofold. First, to examine what beliefs, if any, underlie (a) the Pyrrhonist’s desire for ataraxia and his account of how this state may be attained, and (b) his philanthropic therapy, which seeks to induce, by argument, ejpochv and ataraxia in the Dogmatists. Second, to determine whether the Pyrrhonist’s philanthropy and his search for and attainment of ataraxia are, as scholars have generally believed, essential aspects of his stance.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • The Pyrrhonian Argument from Possible Disagreement.Diego E. Machuca - 2011 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 93 (2):148-161.
    In his Pyrrhonian Outlines , Sextus Empiricus employs an argument based upon the possibility of disagreement in order to show that one should not assent to a Dogmatic claim to which at present one cannot oppose a rival claim. The use of this argument seems to be at variance with the Pyrrhonian stance, both because it does not seem to accord with the definition of Skepticism and because the argument appears to entail that the search for truth is doomed to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Ancient Skepticism: Overview.Diego E. Machuca - 2011 - Philosophy Compass 6 (4):234-245.
    Scholarship on ancient skepticism has undergone a remarkable renaissance in the last three decades. Specialists in ancient philosophy have explored the complex history of the Greco‐Roman skeptical traditions and discussed difficult philological and exegetical issues. But they have also assessed the philosophical significance of the various ancient skeptical outlooks. In this first paper, I provide a general presentation of this area of study, while in the two subsequent articles I will focus on some of the topics that have been the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Agrippan Pyrrhonism and the Challenge of Disagreement.Diego E. Machuca - 2015 - Journal of Philosophical Research 40:23-39.
    This paper argues for the following three claims. First, the Agrippan mode from disagreement does not play a secondary role in inducing suspension of judgment. Second, the Pyrrhonist is not committed to the criteria of justification underlying the Five Modes of Agrippa, which nonetheless does not prevent him from non-doxastically assenting to them. And third, some recent objections to Agrippan Pyrrhonism raised by analytic epistemologists and experimental philosophers fail to appreciate the Pyrrhonist's ad hominem style of argumentation and the real (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Establishing the Logos of Melissus: A Note on Chapter 1, Hippocrates’ De natura hominis.Benjamin Harriman - 2021 - Archai: Revista de Estudos Sobre as Origens Do Pensamento Ocidental 31.
    The earliest mention of Melissus of Samos by name is found in the first chapter of the Hippocratic De natura hominis. In the following note, I attempt to examine what is meant by the reference Melissus’ ‘logos’ in this work and suggest, against previous accounts, including Galen’s, that it has little to do with his commitment to monism. Rather Melissus’ logos is better understood as his referring to his strategy for demonstrating such a conclusion, especially his use of a supplemental (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Stoic concept of phantasia: from Zeno to Chrysippus.Aldo Dinucci - 2017 - Archai: Revista de Estudos Sobre as Origens Do Pensamento Ocidental 21:33-37.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ancient skepticism.Leo Groarke - forthcoming - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Speusippus.Russell Dancy - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Xenocrates.Russell Dancy - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Pyrrhonism and the Law of Non-Contradiction.Diego E. Machuca - 2011 - In D. E. Machuca (ed.), Pyrrhonism in Ancient, Modern, and Contemporary Philosophy. Springer.
    The question of whether the Pyrrhonist adheres to certain logical principles, criteria of justification, and inference rules is of central importance for the study of Pyrrhonism. Its significance lies in that, whereas the Pyrrhonist describes his philosophical stance and argues against the Dogmatists by means of what may be considered a rational discourse, adherence to any such principles, criteria, and rules does not seem compatible with the radical character of his skepticism. Hence, if the Pyrrhonist does endorse them, one must (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • El escepticismo ético de Sexto Empírico.Diego E. Machuca - 2006 - Dissertation, Universidad de Buenos Aires
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark