Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. "When" do Scientists Prefer to Vary their Experiments?H. M. Collins - 1984 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 15 (2):169.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Introduction: have we ever been ‘transnational’? Towards a history of science across and beyond borders.Simone Turchetti, Néstor Herran & Soraya Boudia - 2012 - British Journal for the History of Science 45 (3):319-336.
    In recent years, historians have debated the prospect of offering new ‘transnational’ or ‘global’ perspectives in their studies. This paper introduces the reader to this special issue by analysing characteristics, merits and flaws of these approaches. It then considers how historians of science have practised transnational history without, however, paying sufficient attention to the theoretical foundations of this approach. Its final part illustrates what benefits may derive from the application of transnational history in the field. In particular, we suggest looking (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Arguments for a non‐Whiggish hindsight: Counterfactuals and the sociology of knowledge.William Lynch - 1989 - Social Epistemology 3 (4):361 – 365.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Literate acts and the emergent social structure of science: A critical synthesis.Charles Bazerman - 1987 - Social Epistemology 1 (4):295 – 310.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Decentering sociology: Synthetic dyes and social theory.Andrew Pickering - 2005 - Perspectives on Science 13 (3):352-405.
    : This essay addresses the difficulties that sociology as a discipline continues to experience in grasping the relations between technology, science and the social. I argue that these difficulties stem from a resolute centering of sociology on the social, which follows a generically Durkheimian blueprint. I elaborate a response to these difficulties which derives from recent lines of work in science and technology studies, and which entails a decentering of the social relative to the material and the conceptual, in terms (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Reflections on the preservation of recent scientific heritage in dispersed university collections.Nicholas Jardine - 2013 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 44 (4):735-743.
    The bulk of the significant recent scientific heritage of universities is not to be found in accredited science museums or collections employed in research. Rather it is located in a wide variety of more informal collections, assemblages and accumulations. The selection and documentation of such materials is very often unsystematic and many of them are vulnerable to changes of staff, relocation and, above all, shortage of space. Following a survey of views on the values of the recent material heritage of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Immanent philosophy of X.Robin Hendry - unknown
    In this paper I examine the relationship between historians, philosophers and sociologists of science, and indeed scientists themselves. I argue that they co-habit a shared intellectual territory ; and they should be able to do so peacefully, and with mutual respect, even if they disagree radically about how to describe the methods and results of science. I then go on to explore some of the challenges to mutually respectful cohabitation between history, philosophy and sociology of science. I conclude by identifying (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Einführung in das Thema.Dietrich Von Engelhardt - 1987 - Berichte Zur Wissenschaftsgeschichte 10 (3):129-139.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Deconstruction, postmodernism and philosophy of science: Some Epistemo‐critical bearings.Christopher Norris - 1998 - Cultural Values 2 (1):18-50.
    This essay argues a case for viewing Derrida's work in the context of recent French epistemology and philosophy of science; more specifically, the critical‐rationalist approach exemplified by thinkers such as Bachelard and Canguilhem. I trace this line of descent principally through Derrida's essay ‘White Mythology: Metaphor in the Text of Philosophy’. My conclusions are (1) that we get Derrida wrong if we read him as a fargone antirealist for whom there is nothing ‘outside the text'; (2) that he provides some (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Autonomy and Objectivity of Science.Jouni-Matti Kuukkanen - 2012 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 26 (3):309-334.
    This article deals with the problematic concepts of the rational and the social, which have been typically seen as dichotomous in the history and philosophy of science literature. I argue that this view is mistaken and that the social can be seen as something that enables rationality in science, and further, that a scientific community as well as an individual can be taken as an epistemic subject. Furthermore, I consider how scientific communities could be seen as freely acting and choosing (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • What does the double hermeneutic explain/justify?William Lynch - 1993 - Social Epistemology 7 (2):193 – 204.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Science, Marx, and history: Are there still research frontiers?Harold Dorn - 2000 - Perspectives on Science 8 (3):223-254.
    : Half a century of political Marxism and Soviet social science deflected Marxist thought from its canonical sources. Communism and Marxism were so intertwined by events of the twentieth century that it is difficult to see what remains of the latter after the demise of the former. Specifically, three foundational principles--"being determines consciousness," the Asiatic Mode of Production, and "the ideas of the ruling class are the ruling ideas"--have been corrupted by heartfelt ideological commitments. A review of those principles against (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Anti-Latour.David Bloor - 1999 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 30 (1):81-112.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   111 citations  
  • An Issue of Originality and Priority: The Correspondence and Theories of Oxidative Phosphorylation of Peter Mitchell and Robert J.P. Williams, 1961–1980.Bruce H. Weber & John N. Prebble - 2006 - Journal of the History of Biology 39 (1):125-163.
    In the same year, 1961, Peter D. Mitchell and Robert R.J.P. Williams both put forward hypotheses for the mechanism of oxidative phosphorylation in mitochondria and photophosphorylation in chloroplasts. Mitchell's proposal was ultimately adopted and became known as the chemiosmotic theory. Both hypotheses were based on protons and differed markedly from the then prevailing chemical theory originally proposed by E.C. Slater in 1953, which by 1961 was failing to account for a number of experimental observations. Immediately following the publication of Williams's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Is science metaphysically neutral?Iris Fry - 2012 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 43 (3):665-673.
    This paper challenges the claim that science is metaphysically neutral upheld by contenders of the separation of peacefully co-existent science and religion and by evolutionary theists. True, naturalistic metaphysical claims can neither be refuted nor proved and are thus distinct from empirical hypotheses. However, metaphysical assumptions not only regulate the theoretical and empirical study of nature, but are increasingly supported by the growing empirical body of science. This historically evolving interaction has contributed to the development of a naturalistic worldview that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Peculiarities of the Americans or Are There National Styles in the Sciences?Nathan Reingold - 1991 - Science in Context 4 (2):347-366.
    The ArgumentOver the years national styles have been invoked or denigrated in the writing of the history of science. This paper is an attempt to give the concept of national style a degree of precision and clarity enabling scholars to understand when and how it may be invoked and when and how its use would be dubious or even forbidden. The example of the United States of America is used because the history of the sciences in the United States was (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • How it all began: From the enlightenment in national context to revolution in history.Mikuláš Teich - 2003 - History of Science 41 (3):335-343.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Disciplinary Networks and Bounding: Scientific Communication Between Science and Technology Studies and the History of Science. [REVIEW]Frédéric Vandermoere & Raf Vanderstraeten - 2012 - Minerva 50 (4):451-470.
    This article examines the communication networks within and between science and technology studies (STS) and the history of science. In particular, journal relatedness data are used to analyze some of the structural features of their disciplinary identities and relationships. The results first show that, although the history of science is more than half a century older than STS, the size of the STS network is more than twice that of the history of science network. Further, while a majority of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Bloor's bluff: Behaviourism and the strong programme.Peter Slezak - 1991 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 5 (3):241 – 256.
    Abstract The accumulated case studies in the Sociology of Scientific Knowledge have been taken to establish the Strong Programme's thesis that beliefs have social causes in contradistinction to psychological ones. This externalism is essentially a commitment to the stimulus control of behaviour which was the principal tenet of orthodox Skinnerian Behaviorism. Offered as ?straight forward scientific hypotheses? these claims of social determination are asserted to be ?beyond dispute?. However, the causes of beliefs and especially their contents has also been the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Perfecting the machine: Instrumental rationality and the bureaucratic ideologies of the state.Bruce Berman - 1990 - World Futures 28 (1):141-161.
    (1990). Perfecting the machine: Instrumental rationality and the bureaucratic ideologies of the state. World Futures: Vol. 28, Cross-Cultural Dialogue, pp. 141-161.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Foundations of social epistemics.Alvin I. Goldman - 1987 - Synthese 73 (1):109 - 144.
    A conception of social epistemology is articulated with links to studies of science and opinion in such disciplines as history, sociology, and political science. The conception is evaluative, though, rather than purely descriptive. Three types of evaluative approaches are examined but rejected: relativism, consensualism, and expertism. A fourth, truth-linked, approach to intellectual evaluation is then advocated: social procedures should be appraised by their propensity to foster true belief. Standards of evaluation in social epistemics would be much the same as those (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • Innovation and change in the production of knowledge.Harvey Goldman - 1995 - Social Epistemology 9 (3):211 – 232.
    (1995). Innovation and change in the production of knowledge. Social Epistemology: Vol. 9, Knowledge (EX) Change, pp. 211-232. doi: 10.1080/02691729508578789.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On regulating what is known: A way to social epistemology.Steve Fuller - 1987 - Synthese 73 (1):145 - 183.
    This paper lays the groundwork for normative-yet-naturalistic social epistemology. I start by presenting two scenarios for the history of epistemology since Kant, one in which social epistemology is the natural outcome and the other in which it represents a not entirely satisfactory break with classical theories of knowledge. Next I argue that the current trend toward naturalizing epistemology threatens to destroy the distinctiveness of the sociological approach by presuming that it complements standard psychological and historical approaches. I then try to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • (1 other version)Essay Review: What is the History of Science Really Like?, Science: A Four Thousand Year HistoryScience: A Four Thousand Year History. FaraPatricia . Pp. xii + 408. £20. ISBN 978-0-19-922689-4.Iwan Rhys Morus - 2009 - History of Science 47 (3):359-366.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What can the history of AI learn from the history of science?Alison E. Adam - 1990 - AI and Society 4 (3):232-241.
    There have been few attempts, so far, to document the history of artificial intelligence. It is argued that the “historical sociology of scientific knowledge” can provide a broad historiographical approach for the history of AI, particularly as it has proved fruitful within the history of science in recent years. The article shows how the sociology of knowledge can inform and enrich four types of project within the history of AI; organizational history; AI viewed as technology; AI viewed as cognitive science (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Gendered knowledge — Epistemology and artificial intelligence.Alison Adam - 1993 - AI and Society 7 (4):311-322.
    The paper proposes that gender can be used to explore alternative epistemologies represented within AI systems. Current research on feminist epistemology is reviewed then criticisms of the main philosophical position dominant in AI are outlined. These criticisms say little about epistemology and nothing about gender. It is suggested that the way forward might be found within the sociology of scientific knowledge as its approach is in accord with the postmodernist view of feminist epistemology in seeing knowledge as a cultural product. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Epistemological derangement.Joseph Rouse - 2005 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 36 (4):835-847.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Priestley's Questions: An Historiography Survey.Simon Schaffer - 1984 - History of Science 22 (2):151-183.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Systems of display: the making of anatomical knowledge in Enlightenment Britain.Carin Berkowitz - 2013 - British Journal for the History of Science 46 (3):359-387.
    Late eighteenth- and early nineteenth-century anatomy depended upon a variety of visual displays. Drawings in books, particularly expensive, beautiful and elaborately illustrated books that have been the objects of historians' fascination, were understood to function alongside chalk drawings done in classrooms, casual and formalized experience with animal and human corpses, text describing or contextualizing the images, and preserved specimens. This article argues that British anatomists of the late Enlightenment discovered and taught an intelligible, orderly Nature through comprehensive systems of display. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Yearley's science, technology and social change.Steven Yearley - 1992 - Social Epistemology 6 (1):65 – 71.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The crucial experiment of Wilhelm johannsen.Nils Roll-Hansen - 1989 - Biology and Philosophy 4 (3):303-329.
    I call an experiment “crucial” when it makes possible a decisive choice between conflicting hypotheses. Joharmsen's selection for size and weight within pure lines of beans played a central role in the controversy over continuity or discontinuity in hereditary change, often known as the Biometrician-Mendelian controversy. The “crucial” effect of this experiment was not an instantaneous event, but an extended process of repeating similar experiments and discussing possible objections. It took years before Johannsen's claim about the genetic stability of pure (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Expert systems and human knowledge: A view from the sociology of science. [REVIEW]Brian P. Bloomfield - 1988 - AI and Society 2 (1):17-29.
    After the setbacks suffered in the 1970s as a result of the ‘Lighthill Report’ (Lighthill, 1973), the science of Artificial Intelligence (AI) has undergone a dramatic revival of fortunes in the 1980s. But despite the obvious enormity and complexity of the problems tackled by AI, it still remains rather parochial in relation to the import of alternative though potentially fruitful ideas from other disciplines. With this in mind, the aim of the present paper is to utilise ideas from the sociology (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations