Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. M. Erler, J.E. Heßler and F.M. Petrucci (eds.), Authorities and Authoritative Texts in the Platonist Tradition.Olga Alieva - 2022 - Méthexis 34 (1):179-183.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Antiochus of Ascalon’s ‘Platonic’ Ethics.Franco Trabattoni - 2022 - Elenchos: Rivista di Studi Sul Pensiero Antico 43 (1):85-103.
    This article focuses on the Platonic version of the doctrine of oikeiosis set forth by Piso in Cicero’s De finibus, Book V. The article aims to show that: 1) Cicero’s account, while clearly having Stoic features, is also consistent with the eudaemonistic character of Socrates’ and Plato’s ethics; 2) the replacement of oikeiosis with “assimilation to god”, attested in a passage of the Anonymous Commentary on Plato’s Theaetetus, derives from the intent to remove Epicurean egoistic connotations from Plato’s ethics; according (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Thales – the ‘first philosopher’? A troubled chapter in the historiography of philosophy.Lea Cantor - 2022 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 30 (5):727-750.
    It is widely believed that the ancient Greeks thought that Thales was the first philosopher, and that they therefore maintained that philosophy had a Greek origin. This paper challenges these assumptions, arguing that most ancient Greek thinkers who expressed views about the history and development of philosophy rejected both positions. I argue that not even Aristotle presented Thales as the first philosopher, and that doing so would have undermined his philosophical commitments and interests. Beyond Aristotle, the view that Thales was (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The State of the Question in the Study of Plato: Twenty Year Update.Gerald A. Press - 2018 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 56 (1):9-35.
    This article updates “The State of the Question in the Study of Plato” (Southern Journal of Philosophy, 1996) based on research covering the years from 1995–2015. Its three major parts examine: (1) how the mid‐twentieth‐century consensus has fared, (2) whether the new trends identified in that article have continued, and (3) identify trends either new or missed in the original article. On the whole, it shows the continuing decline of dogmatic and nondramatic Plato interpretation and the expansion and ramification of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Plato's Authority and the Formation of Textual Communities.Dirk Baltzly - 2014 - Classical Quarterly 64 (2):793-807.
    It is widely agreed that, in the re-emergence of Platonism as a dogmatic school of philosophy following the demise of the sceptical academy, Plato's works came to have an authoritative status. This paper argues for a particular understanding of what that authority consists in and how it was acquired.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Why Is the ‘Timaeus’ So Important for Middle Platonists (Again)? A New Proposal.Arianna Piazzalunga & Federico Maria Petrucci - 2023 - Méthexis 35 (1):53-73.
    This paper aims to show that the Middle Platonists’ appeal to the Timaeus was grounded in a complex and effective philosophical reasoning: the Middle Platonists conceived of Plato’s text as a web of passages which Plato himself had carefully established. Only a few of them were granted a qualified priority, namely, those offering a complete and comprehensive philosophical account of the key elements which the Platonists regarded as fundamental. This will allow us to show that the Middle Platonists’ preference for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Iamblichus Apvd Simpl. Corollarivm de Tempore 794.21–7 Diels.Jeffrey M. Johns - 2021 - Classical Quarterly 71 (2):849-855.
    In his commentary on theTimaeus, the Neoplatonist Iamblichus argues that time is logically antecedent to change inasmuch as time is no mere aspect of change. Naturally, scholars appraise this thesis in light of Neoplatonic metaphysics. Nevertheless, they neglect the philological framing of this thesis, and thence the philosophical implications thereof. Only J.M. Dillon acknowledges this framing, though even Dillon does not acknowledge the philosophical implications thereof. This article illustrates the logic of said thesis vis-à-vis the Iamblichean exegesis ofTi. 38b7–c1 (Iambl.apudSimpl.in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Galen, Divination and the Status of Medicine.Peter van Nuffelen - 2014 - Classical Quarterly 64 (1):337-352.
    Galen's stories about his successes in predicting the development of an illness belong to the best-known anecdotes drawn from his writings. Brilliant pieces of self-presentation, they set Galen apart from his peers, who tried to cover up their ignorance by levelling accusations of magic and divination against their superior colleague. These accusations are usually interpreted as very real threats, as Roman law punished illicit magic and divination. Pointing out that Galen sometimes likes to present himself as amantisand a prophet, others (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Why Care Whether Scepticism is Different from Other Philosophies?Richard Bett - 2015 - Philosophie Antique 15:27-52.
    L’article porte sur la façon dont Sextus, dans les derniers chapitres du Livre I des Esquisses pyrrhoniennes, répond aux argumentations qui tendent à rattacher le scepticisme à diverses philosophies plus anciennes. Après une étude de la nature et des sources de ces argumentations à partir du témoignage de Diogène Laërce et d’autres auteurs, et le constat que bien des questions à ce sujet ne peuvent que rester sans réponse, la majeure partie de l’article est consacrée à l’analyse des contre-arguments avancés (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark