Switch to: References

Citations of:

The morality of coercion

Journal of Medical Ethics 26 (5):393-395 (2000)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Rethinking paternalism: an exploration of responses to the Israel Patient's Rights Act 1996.S. Waltho - 2011 - Journal of Medical Ethics 37 (9):540-543.
    Questions of patient autonomy have formed an important part of ethical debate in medicine from at least the post-war period onwards. Although initially important as a counterweight to widespread medical paternalism, recent years have seen a reaction against a widely perceived ‘triumph of autonomy’. In particular, competent patients' refusal of life-saving or clearly beneficial treatment presents complex dilemmas for both healthcare professionals and ethicists. Discussion of the mechanism provided by the Israel Patient's Rights Act of 1996 for ethics committees to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Autonomy, Wellbeing, and the Case of the Refusing Patient.Jukka Varelius - 2005 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 9 (1):117-125.
    A moral problem arises when a patient refuses a treatment that would save her life. Should the patient be treated against her will? According to an influential approach to questions of biomedical ethics, certain considerations pertaining to individual autonomy provide a solution to this problem. According to this approach, we should respect the patient’s autonomy and, since she has made an autonomous decision against accepting the treatment, she should not be treated. This article argues against the view that our answer (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Applying the welfare model to at-own-risk discharges.Lalit Kumar Radha Krishna, Sumytra Menon & Ravindran Kanesvaran - 2017 - Nursing Ethics 24 (5):525-537.
    “At-own-risk discharges” or “self-discharges” evidences an irretrievable breakdown in the patient–clinician relationship when patients leave care facilities before completion of medical treatment and against medical advice. Dissolution of the therapeutic relationship terminates the physician’s duty of care and professional liability with respect to care of the patient. Acquiescence of an at-own-risk discharge by the clinician is seen as respecting patient autonomy. The validity of such requests pivot on the assumptions that the patient is fully informed and competent to invoke an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Treating competent patients by force: the limits and lessons of Israel's Patient's Rights Act.M. L. Gross - 2005 - Journal of Medical Ethics 31 (1):29-34.
    Competent patients who refuse life saving medical treatment present a dilemma for healthcare professionals. On one hand, respect for autonomy and liberty demand that physicians respect a patient’s decision to refuse treatment. However, it is often apparent that such patients are not fully competent. They may not adequately comprehend the benefits of medical care, be overly anxious about pain, or discount the value of their future state of health. Although most bioethicists are convinced that partial autonomy or marginal competence of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Limits to relational autonomy—The Singaporean experience.L. K. R. Krishna, D. S. Watkinson & N. L. Beng - 2015 - Nursing Ethics 22 (3):331-340.
    Recognition that the Principle of Respect for Autonomy fails to work in family-centric societies such as Singapore has recently led to the promotion of relational autonomy as a suitable framework within which to place healthcare decision making. However, empirical data, relating to patient and family opinions and the practices of healthcare professionals in Confucian-inspired Singapore, demonstrate clear limitations on the ability of a relational autonomy framework to provide the anticipated compromise between prevailing family decision-making norms and adopted Western led atomistic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Applying the welfare model to at-own-risk discharges.Lalit Kumar Radha Krishna, Sumytra Menon & Ravindran Kanesvaran - 2017 - Nursing Ethics 24 (5):525-537.
    “At-own-risk discharges” or “self-discharges” evidences an irretrievable breakdown in the patient–clinician relationship when patients leave care facilities before completion of medical treatment and against medical advice. Dissolution of the therapeutic relationship terminates the physician’s duty of care and professional liability with respect to care of the patient. Acquiescence of an at-own-risk discharge by the clinician is seen as respecting patient autonomy. The validity of such requests pivot on the assumptions that the patient is fully informed and competent to invoke an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Poverty: Not a Justification for Banning Physician‐Assisted Death.Lindsey M. Freeman, Susannah L. Rose & Stuart J. Youngner - 2018 - Hastings Center Report 48 (6):38-46.
    Many critics of the legalization of physician‐assisted death oppose it in part because they fear it will further disadvantage those who are already economically disadvantaged. This argument points to a serious problem of how economic considerations can influence medical decisions, but in the context of PAD, the concern is not borne out. We will provide empirical evidence suggesting that concerns about money influence medical decisions throughout the full course of illness, but at the end of life, financial pressure is much (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Dialectic of Autonomy and Beneficence in the Standard Argument for ‘Death with Dignity'.Bell Jeremy Raymond - 2016 - Solidarity: The Journal of Catholic Social Thought and Secular Ethics 6 (1):Article 3.
    Philosophers who defend a person’s right, under certain circumstances, to end his own life or to have a physician end it for him typically appeal both to respect for patient autonomy and to considerations of beneficence. Neither autonomy alone nor beneficence alone can ground a persuasive case for euthanasia. I argue, however, that the standard argument for euthanasia is unsound. It is not possible to combine the principles of autonomy and beneficence in such a way as to justify euthanasia for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark