Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. I Ought, Therefore I Can.Peter B. M. Vranas - 2007 - Philosophical Studies 136 (2):167-216.
    I defend the following version of the ought-implies-can principle: (OIC) by virtue of conceptual necessity, an agent at a given time has an (objective, pro tanto) obligation to do only what the agent at that time has the ability and opportunity to do. In short, obligations correspond to ability plus opportunity. My argument has three premises: (1) obligations correspond to reasons for action; (2) reasons for action correspond to potential actions; (3) potential actions correspond to ability plus opportunity. In the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   136 citations  
  • ‘Ought’ Does Not Imply ‘Can’.Moti Mizrahi - 2009 - Philosophical Frontiers 4 (1):19-35.
    According to the Ought-Implies-Can principle (OIC), an agent ought to perform a certain action only if the agent can perform that action. Proponents of OIC interpret this supposed implication in several ways. Some argue that the implication in question is a logical one, namely, entailment. Some think that the relation between ‘ought’ and ‘can’ is a relation of presupposition. Still others argue that ‘ought’ conversationally implicates ‘can’. Opponents of OIC offer a variety of counterexamples in an attempt to show that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Virtue ethics and anti-theory.Robert B. Louden - 1990 - Philosophia 20 (1-2):93-114.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Sollen und Können.Jens Timmermann - 2003 - History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 6 (1):113-122.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • God, Tragic Dilemmas, and the Problem of Gratuitous Evil.Arash Naraghi - 2022 - Dialogue 61 (2):311-324.
    RésuméDe nombreux philosophes ont soutenu que l'existence du mal gratuit est la plus sérieuse objection contre l'existence d'un Dieu absolument parfait. Je soutiens que l'idée d'un dilemme moral (ou, plus précisément, d'un dilemmetragique) peut (1) fournir une justification morale pour que Dieu permette l'existence du mal gratuit, ou (2) offrir une théodicée de la tragédie divine pour expliquer pourquoi les maux de ce monde ne sont pas nécessairement gratuits ou, s'ils le sont, pourquoi ils ne peuvent pas fournir une preuve (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Moral Dilemmas and Collective Responsibilities.Jessica B. Payson - 2009 - Essays in Philosophy 10 (2):160-182.
    In this paper, I work within Ruth Marcus’s account of the source of moral dilemmas and articulate the implications of her theory for collective responsibility. As an extension to Marcus’s work, I explore what her account means for the moral emotions and responsibilities of those complicit in perpetuating unjust systems of a non-ideal world from which moral dilemmas arise. This move necessitates shifting away from the primacy of control. That one is born into unjust systems one had no hand in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Situationist deontic logic.Sven Ove Hansson - 1997 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 26 (4):423-448.
    Situationist deontic logic is a model of that fraction of normative discourse which refers to only one situation and one set of alternatives. As we can see from a whole series of well-known paradoxes, standard deontic logic (SDL) is seriously mistaken even at the situationist level. In this paper it is shown how a more realistic deontic logic can be based on the assumption that prescriptive predicates satisfy the property of contranegativity. A satisfactory account of situation-specific norms is a necessary (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • But what should I do?Sven Ove Hansson - 1999 - Philosophia 27 (3-4):433-440.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations