Switch to: References

Citations of:

Arabic and islamic philosophy of language and logic

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2008)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Aristotle, Arabic.Marc Geoffroy - 2011 - In H. Lagerlund (ed.), Encyclopedia of Medieval Philosophy. Springer. pp. 105--116.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Post-avicennan logicians on the subject matter of logic: Some thirteenth- and fourteenth-century discussions.Khaled El-Rouayheb - 2012 - Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 22 (1):69-90.
    In the thirteenth century, the influential logician Afḍal al-Dīn al-Khūnajī departed from the Avicennan view that the subject matter of logic is “second intentions”. For al-Khūnajī, the subject matter of logic is “the objects of conception and assent”. His departure elicited intense and sometimes abstruse discussions in the course of subsequent centuries. Prominent supporters of Khūnajī's view on the subject matter of logic included Kātibī, Ibn Wāṣil and Taftāzānī. Defenders of Avicenna's view included Ṭūsī, Samarqandī and Quṭb al-Dīn al-Rāzī. This (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Analytic Philosophy of Religion.Graham Oppy - 2021 - Saudi Journal of Philosophical Studies 2:163-79.
    This paper provides an overview of 'analytic' philosophy of religion. It begins with a historical sketch. It then examines some of the kinds of questions that are investigated by 'analytic' philosophers of religion. It concludes with brief discussion of possible futures for 'analytic' philosophy of religion. There is also a very short appendix on the treatment of Islam and Arabic philosophy within 'analytic' philosophy of religion.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Two Indian dialectical logics: saptabhangi and catuskoti.Fabien Schang - 2010 - Journal of the Indian Council of Philosophical Research 27 (1):45-75.
    A rational interpretation is proposed for two ancient Indian logics: the Jaina saptabhaṅgī, and the Mādhyamika catuṣkoṭi. It is argued that the irrationality currently imputed to these logics relies upon some philosophical preconceptions inherited from Aristotelian metaphysics. This misunderstanding can be corrected in two steps: by recalling their assumptions about truth; by reconstructing their ensuing theory of judgment within a common conceptual framework.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Conservation and Causation in Avicenna's Metaphysics.Emann Allebban - 2018 - Dissertation, Mcgill University
    This dissertation examines Avicenna's theory of efficient causation in light of his approach to central problems in metaphysics, from the proof of the Necessary Existent to his emanative cosmology. Avicenna provides an internally coherent metaphysical account of efficient causation. A metaphysical account of the efficient cause explains the existence of the effect or essence in a way that is not explained by the causes of motion, as investigated in physics. That is, a full explanation of the cause of the existence (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Avicenna on Possibility and Necessity.Saloua Chatti - 2014 - History and Philosophy of Logic 35 (4):332-353.
    In this paper, I raise the following problem: How does Avicenna define modalities? What oppositional relations are there between modal propositions, whether quantified or not? After giving Avicenna's definitions of possibility, necessity and impossibility, I analyze the modal oppositions as they are stated by him. This leads to the following results: The relations between the singular modal propositions may be represented by means of a hexagon. Those between the quantified propositions may be represented by means of two hexagons that one (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Al-Taftāzānī on the Liar Paradox.David Sanson & Ahmed Alwishah - 2016 - Oxford Studies in Medieval Philosophy 4 (1).
    Al-Taftāzānī introduces the Liar Paradox, in a commentary on al-Rāzī, in a short passage that is part of a polemic against the ethical rationalism of the Muʿtazila. In this essay, we consider his remarks and their place in the history of the Liar Paradox in Arabic Logic. In the passage, al-Taftāzānī introduces Liar Cycles into the tradition, gives the paradox a puzzling name—the fallacy of the “irrational root” —which became standard, and suggests a connection between the paradox and what it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Landulph Caracciolo.Christopher Schabel - 2011 - In H. Lagerlund (ed.), Encyclopedia of Medieval Philosophy. Springer. pp. 681--684.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Introduction: Double Intentionality.Michela Summa, Martin Klein & Philipp Schmidt - 2021 - Topoi 41 (1):93-109.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • An Inquiry on Fakhr al-Dīn Rāzī’s Authorship of Al-Manṭiq al-kabīr.Asadollah Fallahi - 2021 - History and Philosophy of Logic 42 (3):224-246.
    It is quite common among historians of Arabic logic to attribute MS Aḥmad iii, no. 3401, entitled Al-manṭiq al-kabīr, to Fakhr al-Dīn Rāzī. This view is expressed explicitly...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Al-Fārābī Metaphysics, and the Construction of Social Knowledge: Is Deception Warranted if it Leads to Happiness?Nicholas Andrew Oschman - unknown
    When questioning whether political deception can be ethically warranted, two competing intuitions jump to the fore. First, political deception is a fact of human life, used in the realpolitik of governance. Second, the ethical warrant of truth asserts itself as inexorably and indefatigably preferable to falsehood. Unfortunately, a cursory examination of the history of philosophy reveals a paucity of models to marry these basic intuitions. Some thinkers (e.g., Augustine, Aquinas, Grotius, Kant, Mill, and Rawls) privilege the truth by neglecting the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation