Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Transcendental Concepts, Transcendental Truths and Objective Validity.Chong-Fuk Lau - 2015 - Kantian Review 20 (3):445-466.
    Kant insists that the use of concepts must be subject to empirical conditions if they are to have objective validity. This article analyses Kants distinction between empirical and transcendental truths. Since transcendental concepts are pure concepts without spatio-temporal content, their objective validity is of the same second-order kind as that of unschematized categories. This characteristic of transcendental concepts implies that the cognitive powers picked out by them are not particular psychological mechanisms, but rather abstract functional structures. Transcendental concepts owe their (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Mind, Knowledge and Reality: Themes from Kant.Quassim Cassam - 1998 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 43:321-348.
    According to what might be described as ‘humanist’ approaches to epistemology, the fundamental task of epistemology is to investigate the nature, scope and origins of human knowledge. Evidently, what we can know depends upon the nature of our cognitive faculties, including our senses and our understanding. Since there may be significant differences between human cognitive faculties and those of other beings, it would seem that an investigation of the nature, scope and origins of human knowledge must therefore concern itself, in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mind, Knowledge and Reality: Themes from Kant.Quassim Cassam - 1998 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 43:321-348.
    According to what might be described as ‘humanist’ approaches to epistemology, the fundamental task of epistemology is to investigate the nature, scope and origins of human knowledge. Evidently, what we can know depends upon the nature of our cognitive faculties, including our senses and our understanding. Since there may be significant differences between human cognitive faculties and those of other beings, it would seem that an investigation of the nature, scope and origins of human knowledge must therefore concern itself, in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Has Strawson Refuted Scepticism about Other Minds?J. L. Martin - 1974 - Philosophy 49 (190):420 - 428.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Contemporary Arguments for a Geometry of Visual Experience.Phillip John Meadows - 2009 - European Journal of Philosophy 19 (3):408-430.
    Abstract: In this paper I consider recent attempts to establish that the geometry of visual experience is a spherical geometry. These attempts, offered by Gideon Yaffe, James van Cleve and Gordon Belot, follow Thomas Reid in arguing for an equivalency of a geometry of ‘visibles’ and spherical geometry. I argue that although the proposed equivalency is successfully established by the strongest form of the argument, this does not warrant any conclusion about the geometry of visual experience. I argue, firstly, that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Transcendental aspects, ontological commitments and naturalistic elements in Nietzsche's thought.Béatrice Han‐Pile - 2009 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 52 (2):179 – 214.
    Nietzsche's views on knowledge have been interpreted in at least three incompatible ways - as transcendental, naturalistic or proto-deconstructionist. While the first two share a commitment to the possibility of objective truth, the third reading denies this by highlighting Nietzsche's claims about the necessarily falsifying character of human knowledge (his so-called error theory). This paper examines the ways in which his work can be construed as seeking ways of overcoming the strict opposition between naturalism and transcendental philosophy whilst fully taking (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Should philosophers take lessons from quantum theory?Christopher Norris - 1999 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 42 (3 & 4):311 – 342.
    This essay examines some of the arguments in David Deutsch's book The Fabric of Reality , chief among them its case for the so-called many-universe interpretation of quantum mechanics (QM), presented as the only physically and logically consistent solution to the QM paradoxes of wave/particle dualism, remote simultaneous interaction, the observer-induced 'collapse of the wave-packet', etc. The hypothesis assumes that all possible outcomes are realized in every such momentary 'collapse', since the observer splits off into so many parallel, coexisting, but (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Reply to Longuenesse. [REVIEW]Quassim Cassam - 2008 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 77 (2):525-531.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • An expressivist interpretation of Kant's “I think” 1.Wolfgang Freitag & Katharina Kraus - 2022 - Noûs 56 (1):110-132.
    Kant's theory of cognition centrally builds on his conception of self‐consciousness and the transcendental use of the phrase “I think”: the ability to add the phrase “I think” to a representation is a necessary condition of the ability to cognize objects. The paper argues that “I think”, rather than denoting the content of a predicative judgement, is typically an expression of the subject's thinking. It expresses a kind of self‐consciousness that, without assertively representing the subject itself, indicates that representational contents (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Liberal naturalism, objectivity and the autonomy of the mental.David Zapero - 2019 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 62 (5):546-564.
    ABSTRACTThe paper distinguishes between two different ways of cashing out the general insight that often goes by the name of ‘liberal naturalism’. The objective is to show how these two different argumentative strategies undergird two fundamentally different approaches to the project of elucidating the specificity of mental phenomena. On one approach, the central concern of such a project is the ontological status of subjective conscious phenomena; on the other, the central concern is the irreducibility of parochial capacities in the adoption (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is svasaṃvitti transcendental? A tentative reconstruction following Śāntarakṣita.Dan Arnold - 2005 - Asian Philosophy 15 (1):77 – 111.
    There has emerged in recent years the recognition that the characteristically Buddhist doctrine of svasa vitti 2 (‘apperception’, as I will render it for reasons to become clear presently) was vari...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Reform and/or Revolution? Comments on Karin de Boer, Kant’s Reform of Metaphysics.Paul Franks - 2022 - Kantian Review 27 (1):127-132.
    Karin de Boer has given the best account so far of the reform of Wolffian metaphysics that Kant promised. But does such a reform cohere with the revolutionary goal that Kant also affirmed? Standpoint is singled out as the central meta-concept of Kant’s revolutionary goal, and it is argued that, in the second and third critiques, Kant himself developed his revolutionary insight into the perspectival character of both concept and judgement in ways that he did not anticipate at the time (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Chapter 3 Kant as a Revolutionary.Sheila Webb - 2020 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 54 (6):1534-1545.
    Journal of Philosophy of Education, EarlyView.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kant on duty in the groundwork.Benjamin Ferguson - 2012 - Res Publica 18 (4):303-319.
    Barbara Herman offers an interpretation of Kant's Groundwork on which an action has moral worth if the primary motive for the action is the motive of duty. She offers this approach in place of Richard Henson's sufficiency-based interpretation, according to which an action has moral worth when the motive of duty is sufficient by itself to generate the action. Noa Latham criticizes Herman's account and argues that we cannot make sense of the position that an agent can hold multiple motives (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Hermann von Helmholtz: The problem of kantian influence.S. P. Fullinwider - 1990 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 21 (1):41-55.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Chapter 6 Mind‐Dependent Views of Knowledge.Sheila Webb - 2020 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 54 (6):1581-1595.
    Journal of Philosophy of Education, EarlyView.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Chapter 11 Contrasting Readings of Kant.Sheila Webb - 2020 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 54 (6):1658-1672.
    Journal of Philosophy of Education, EarlyView.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Can Transcendental Philosophy Endorse Fallibilism?Gabriele Gava - 2011 - Contemporary Pragmatism 8 (1):133-151.
    The aim of this paper is to apply Charles S. Peirce's pragmatic method to establishing if proponents of transcendental arguments could hold the conclusions of their arguments to be fallibly known. I will thus propose a pragmatic clarification of the concepts of a priority, necessity, and infallibility in order to ascertain if these concepts are unavoidably related or not. I will argue that an a priori knowable necessary proposition is not in principle indubitable, whereas a proposition infallibly known is so. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Transcendental Arguments: Superfluity and Scepticism.Scott Stapleford - 2005 - Theoria 71 (4):333-367.
    The paper is a sustained analysis of some recent work on transcendental arguments with a view to assessing both its relevance to Kant's philosophy and its historical accuracy. Robert Stem's reading of Kant's philosophical aims is examined and criticized narrowly, and Barry Stroud's influential objection to transcendental arguments as a class is shown to be harmless. Kant is presented as a friend rather than a foe of scepticism, and his 'proto-verificationist' criterion of meaning is shown to underpin, rather than undermine, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hermann Von helmholtz: The problem of Kantian influence.S. P. Fullinwider - 1990 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 21 (1):41-55.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • A Spirit of Trust: A Reading of Hegel's Phenomenology by Robert Brandom (Harvard University Press, 2019).Fintan Mallory - 2021 - Philosophy 96 (4):675-682.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • La question des jugements analytiques et des jugements synthétiques chez Kant et chez Wittgenstein.Josette Lanteigne - 1992 - Dialogue 31 (2):255-.
    La confrontation Kant/Wittgenstein qui se dessine ici n'a pas pour objectif principal de présenter les doctrines des deux auteurs. Il s'agit plutôt de marier ces pensées qui ne le désirent pas, de profiter de la confrontation pour faire avancer le débat. Quel débat? Contrairement à I'ordre historique, il tire son origine de Wittgenstein: comment faut-il comprendre les prorèmes que soulève Wittgenstein, les interdits qu'il pose? Certaines de ses affirmations ne peuvent tout simplement pas être des jugements analytiques, aurait dit Kant. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Concepts of the Sceptic: Transcendental Arguments and Other Minds.G. W. Smith - 1974 - Philosophy 49 (188):149 - 168.
    Strawson's attempt to refute scepticism about the existence of other minds has itself been a popular target of sceptical criticism. But the very persistence of the attacks suggests that no clinching rebuttal has yet been produced. One of the earliest and still one of the most effective responses to Strawson is Ayer's celebrated paper ‘The Concept of a Person’, in which he reasserts the position of classical empiricist scepticism on the existence of other minds. By reinterpreting and partly reconstructing Strawson's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Two Standpoints on the Will.Daniel Guevara - 1997 - Kantian Review 1:82-114.
    Kant argues that we must regard the will from two mutually exclusive standpoints. One is the natural standpoint, according to which the will is determined entirely by natural causes in conformity with natural law. The other is the standpoint of freedom, according to which the will transcends the laws of nature and is free to determine itself in conformity with its own law. Kant's idea is that a complete account of the will necessarily involves both standpoints, shifting between the two. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Darwin faces Kant: a study in nineteenth-century physiology.S. P. Fullinwider - 1991 - British Journal for the History of Science 24 (1):21-44.
    Recent explorations into Sigmund Freud's intellectual development by Frank Sulloway and Lucille Ritvo have directed attention to the significance of evolutionary theory for psychoanalysis. In this paper I shall pursue the exploration by showing how Darwin was received by members of the so-called Helmholtz circle and certain of Freud's teachers in the University of Vienna medical school. I will make the point that the Leibniz–Kant background of these several scientists was important for this reception. I will argue that the Leibniz–Kant (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Peirce's barrister: an exemplary story of an example in the theory of signs.Anne Freadman - 1991 - History of the Human Sciences 4 (1):93-106.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Knowledge and its Objects: Revisiting the Bounds of Sense.Quassim Cassam - 2016 - European Journal of Philosophy 24 (4):907-919.
    The Kantian project of investigating the necessary structure of experience presupposes answers to three questions: what is the purpose of such an investigation, what is the source of necessary features of experience, and by what means is it possible to establish the necessary structure of experience? This paper is a critical examination of Strawson's answers to these questions in The Bounds of Sense and his later work. The realism that is implicit in The Bounds of Sense is much more explicit (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Graham Bird, The Revolutionary Kant: Introduction.Gordon Brittan - 2011 - Kantian Review 16 (2):211-219.
    The interpretation of Kant's Critical philosophy as a version of traditional idealism has a long history. In spite of Kant's and his commentators’ various attempts to distinguish between traditional and transcendental idealism, his philosophy continues to be construed as committed to various features usually associated with the traditional idealist project. As a result, most often, the accusation is that his Critical philosophy makes too strong metaphysical and epistemological claims.In his The Revolutionary Kant, Graham Bird engages in a systematic and thorough (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Traces of Objectivity: Causality and Probabilities in Quantum Physics.Michel Bitbol - 2011 - Diogenes 58 (4):30-57.
    It is pointed out that the probabilistic character of a theory does not indicate by itself a distancing with respect to the norms of objectification. Instead, the very structure of the calculation of probabilities utilised by this theory is capable of bearing the trace of a constitution of objectivity in Kant’s sense. Accordingly, the procedure of the constitution of objectivity is first studied in standard and in quantum cases with due reference to modern cognitive science. Then, an examination of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Status of the Principles of the Analogies.Gary Banham - 2011 - Kantian Review 16 (2):201-210.
    The interpretation of Kant's Critical philosophy as a version of traditional idealism has a long history. In spite of Kant's and his commentators’ various attempts to distinguish between traditional and transcendental idealism, his philosophy continues to be construed as committed (whether explicitly or implicitly and whether consistently or inconsistently) to various features usually associated with the traditional idealist project. As a result, most often, the accusation is that his Critical philosophy makes too strong metaphysical and epistemological claims.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark